(ok)resenha momilgliano

Upload: joao-victor-lanna

Post on 06-Jul-2018

218 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/17/2019 (Ok)Resenha Momilgliano

    1/9

    Libertas as a Political Idea at Rome during the Late Republic and Early Principate by Ch.

    WirszubskiReview by: Arnaldo MomiglianoThe Journal of Roman Studies, Vol. 41, Parts 1 and 2 (1951), pp. 146-153Published by: Society for the Promotion of Roman StudiesStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/298106 .

    Accessed: 12/06/2014 17:39

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

     .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of 

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

     .

    Society for the Promotion of Roman Studies is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend

    access to The Journal of Roman Studies.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.228 on Thu, 12 Jun 2014 17:39:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=sprshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/298106?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/298106?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=sprs

  • 8/17/2019 (Ok)Resenha Momilgliano

    2/9

    REVIEW AND DISCUSSION

    CH. WIRSZUBSKI,

    LIBERTAS AS A

    POLITICAL

    IDEA A T ROME DURING THE LATE REPUBLIC

    AND EARLY PRINCIPATE (Cambridge Classical

    Studies). Cambridge University Press, 1I950.

    Pp. XI +

    I

    82.

    I5s.

    A pilgrim to Cambridge (from Jerusalem),

    iMir.

    WVirszubski

    has entered into the spirit of the

    place and has written a little book which Lord Acton

    will read with pleasure in the Elysian Fields.

    Havring perused

    it in no less distinguished a place-the Ashmolean

    lMluseum-I

    found it entirely

    enjoyable and

    would like to recommend it to those who are disturbed by the

    present trends in

    the

    study

    of

    Late Republican and Early Imperial History.

    Naivre apologists for Roman

    '

    vrirtues

    '

    are

    only too obvriously discredited-except perhaps in

    some numismatic cabinets; but the Realpolitiker

    who are replacing them are

    not

    more impressivre(cf.

    H. Last,

    Gnomizon

    2,

    I950, 360).

    iVMr.

    Wirszubski,

    unruffled by

    the

    recent, apparently unexpected,

    discovrery that Cicero liked good dinners, that the

    Roman populace

    took bribes and

    that Octavrian's

    followers asked for rewards, understands Cicero

    well, interprets Tacitus correctly,

    and

    knows what

    Thrasea stood for.

    The discussion of

    a

    book

    one likes can

    easily

    outgrow any tolerable proportions. I must confine

    my review to two points. First I shall probe the foundations

    of Mr. Wirszubski's history of Libertas;

    secondly, I shall try to show by one example that the reconsideration of the principles of Libertas

    requires new research in detail.

    I.

    Liberty

    and Libertas.-Two different and,

    to my mind, mutually exclusivre interpretations of

    Libertas havre been defended. According to one, Libertas is a juridical notion

    which, if properly

    analysed, provres

    to

    be identical

    with

    the

    notion of Civritas. Libertas sums up

    the rights of a Roman

    civris as

    MVlommsen aid,

    als

    dieser Rechtsschutz selbst als Biirgerrecht aufgefasst ward, fiel

    diese

    ihre libertas

    mit

    der civitas zusammen'

    (R5in.

    Staatsr.

    iII,

    63). According to the other

    interpretation, Libertas

    is a vague word which usually conceals egoistic interests.

    As Professor Syme

    puts it,

    '

    Liberty

    and

    the

    Laws are

    high-sounding

    words. They will often be rendered,

    on a cool

    estimate,

    as

    privrilege

    and vrested interests

    '

    (The

    RomizanRevolution 59). Also :

    '

    Libertas

    is a

    vrague

    and

    negativre

    notion-freedom from the rule of a

    tyrant

    or

    a faction. It follows that libertas,

    like

    regnuin

    and

    donizitiatio,

    s a

    convrenient term of political

    fraud

    '

    (p.

    I55:

    the whole page is relevant).

    Miir.Wirszubski had to make up his mind whether to choose the former (juridical) or the latter

    (ideological) interpretation of Libertas. He has chosen,

    in my opinion quite correctly, the former.

    It is indeed characteristic of Libertas

    that,

    though so often mentioned

    in

    the heat of political

    discussion,

    it seldom looks like an

    empty

    word. XVhen Libertas is quoted, some more or

    less

    important right

    of

    a Roman

    ' ciris

    '

    is

    usually

    in

    question. H. Kloesel's dissertation

    (I935),

    which

    Syme quotes

    as his

    only

    evidence

    for the thesis that Libertas was a

    v

    ague

    and negativre

    notion

    ',

    provres the contrary. Kloesel's list of passages

    shows that Libertas is often associated by Late

    Republican

    or

    Augustan

    writers

    with precise

    laN-s and institutions: such as

    the yearly magistrates,

    'auctoritas

    senatus

    ',

    the

    tribunes,

    '

    provrocatio',

    agrarian laws, the Lex Porcia, the Leges Tabellariae,

    the ' Lex Cassia

    altera

    ',

    etc. Compared with

    the use of the words

    '

    freedom

    '

    and

    '

    liberty'

    in

    political

    discussions of our

    time,

    the use of Libertas

    in

    Roman

    political struggles

    seems

    altogether

    more

    juridically minded-which,

    of

    course,

    one would

    expect, givren

    the

    persons

    for whom

    Roman

    historians and politicians

    were more

    frequently

    writing.

    Thus, my agreement NwithMr. Wirszubski on the way of approaching his subject could hardly

    be greater (cf.

    YRS

    xxxi,

    I94I,

    i6o;

    XXXII, I942,

    I20).

    But when one comes to laying

    the foundations

    of research

    on Libertas as a

    primarily juridical

    notion there is

    scope

    for

    disagreement.

    iVMr.

    Wirszubski

    is not precise enough to my mind, though

    I

    should

    like to add that,

    evren

    when he

    is not

    perfectly

    clear on

    principles,

    he is

    nevrer

    dangerously

    misleading

    on

    details.

    (i)

    Libertas, we

    would all agree,

    is

    not Liberty, but the process which

    leads from

    Libertas

    to

    Liberty

    is

    a

    continuous one.

    If

    wvestart

    from

    Liberty and go back to

    see what

    the Romans

    knew

    and

    practised

    about

    Liberty,

    there are

    many things

    not treated

    in

    W.

    's book to be

    considered:

    for

    instance,

    freedom of

    travrelling,

    of

    teaching,

    of

    publishing books,

    women's freedom,

    freedom

    of

    trade,

    freedom of

    the

    seas, freedom

    in the matter

    of drinking, eating,

    and dressing,

    freedom

    in

    sexual

    behavriour,

    freedom from want and

    fear,

    etc.

    All

    these freedoms

    may

    or

    may

    not havre

    been

    classified

    by

    the Romans under the

    heading

    of

    Libertas. But

    if

    one

    examines

    Libertas

    in itself-

    to know what the Romans meant

    by

    it-one does not see what

    a

    discussion

    of Libertas

    has

    to do

    with religious freedom or with the sanctity of the home (pp.

    29-30),

    unless evxidence s provided that

    these

    things

    were connected with Libertas, which

    is

    not the

    case.

    Furthermore,

    the evridence on Libertas should

    be

    presented

    in a

    rigorous chronological

    order

    and each author should

    be analysed by himself.

    W;.

    has

    givren

    separate paragraphs to Cicero's

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.228 on Thu, 12 Jun 2014 17:39:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 (Ok)Resenha Momilgliano

    3/9

    REVIEW AND DISCUSSION

    I47

    De Re Publica and De Legibus, and

    to Tacitus, with excellent results, but on the whole he has confined

    himself to desultory quotations.

    One consequence is that

    we

    do not

    know

    from his book

    what

    Cicero, Sallust, Livy, Seneca, Lucan thought about Libertas: whether

    the idea of Libertas was

    a central one for them, what notions they connected with Libertas or

    what aspects of Libertas they

    emphasized, what thoughts they attributed to other persons on Libertas, etc.

    Another consequence is that WV.makes no attempt

    at a

    systematic

    use of the epigraphical

    and

    numismatic evidence and therefore

    does not utilize inscriptions and coins even in those cases

    in which they really help to supplement the literary evidence.

    The Lex Porcia de provocatione

    (?

    I99.

    W. does not seem to be aware

    of difficulties about the Leges Porciae: the subject must be

    re-examinedafter A. H.

    lMJcDonald,

    JRS

    XXXIV,

    I944,

    I9)

    and the Lex Cassia of I37 are apparently

    already connected with Libertas

    on coins before

    Ioo

    B.C. (B.-M.C., Rolz. Rep.

    I,

    I5I,

    I53): the

    evidence quoted by

    WI.

    or both connections

    is not earlier than Cicero. Allusions in terms of Libertas

    to

    the grant of Roman citizenship

    to the Italians havrebeen found on coins of about

    75 B.C.

    (ib.

    i,

    399-403).

    I

    feel uneasy about these coins, but the texts produced by

    IV. for the connection between

    Libertas and the grant of citizenship to the Italians are

    evren

    more unsatisfactory:

    one is the alleged

    utterance of an Italian in Velleius

    II, 27, 2,

    and the

    other is the

    opinion

    of a Greek, Strabo V, 4,

    2,

    p.

    24I.

    Among the inscriptions it will be enough

    to recall the decree of L. Aemilius of

    I89 B.C.

    (Dessau, ILS

    IS)

    which MIommsen's commentary made famous (Hernmes

    II,

    i869,

    261

    Ges.

    Schriften iv,

    S6,

    and Staatsrecht

    iii,

    p. xvii, n.

    I).

    As MNIommsen bserved, Rome discouraged

    serfdom.

    (2) The identification of Civitas

    and

    Libertas requires

    careful analysis. One has

    to

    account for

    what the writers said about it at different times and in different circumstances

    (e.g. Cic., pro

    Caecina 96 ; Livy ii, 5 ;

    Dig.

    49,

    I5, 5,

    2, on wrhich

    cf. MI. Nicolau, Cautsa Liberalis

    1933,

    53),

    keeping in mind the three notions

    which

    inevritably

    contributed to complicate any statement on

    this

    subject: the notion

    of

    Roman

    citizenship, the

    notion or

    suspicion

    that

    all

    men are

    naturally

    free, the notion of men living

    a free life outside Roman citizenship.

    In

    other words one must

    analyse what the texts mean by

    '

    Libertas ex iure Quiritium, civritas ibera, postliminium (on which

    F.

    de Visscher, Festschrift P. Koschaker,

    I, I939, 367,

    will be

    found particularly

    useful),

    capitis

    deminutio

    '. The ordinary tripartition

    of

    capitis deninazutio

    s

    found already

    in

    Gaius

    (i I60-2)

    and

    involves a series of

    problems

    which

    W.

    has not faced.

    He

    says:

    '

    Only

    a

    Roman citizen

    enjoys

    all

    the rights, personal and political, that constitute libertas. The so-called Capitis Deminutio lMledia

    whereby

    a Roman loses

    citizenship

    while

    retaining

    freedom

    does not

    contradict

    this conclusion.

    For

    Capitis

    Deminutio

    Miedia

    means

    loss of

    Roman

    citizenship

    as

    a

    consequence

    of

    the

    acquisition

    of a different

    citizenship' (p. 4). This

    I

    take

    to be

    an

    optimistic

    view. For

    Gaius

    says:

    '

    Minor

    siue media est

    capitis

    deminutio

    cum civitas

    amittitur,

    libertas retinetur:

    quod

    accidit

    ei

    cui

    aqua

    et

    igni

    interdictum fuerit.' The

    principle

    underlying

    the

    tripartition

    of

    the

    '

    deminutio

    '

    is

    explained

    by

    Paulus:

    '

    tria enim sunt

    quae

    habemus, libertatem, civitate;n, famniliam

    (Dig.

    4,

    S,

    II).

    This

    tripartition

    is not

    compatible

    with

    the

    identification

    of

    Ci-vitas

    and Libertas.

    If WN.

    hinks

    (as

    he

    seems to

    imply)

    that the

    tripartitioln

    of

    capitis

    demizinuttio

    s

    already part

    of

    the

    juridical thought

    of

    the Roman

    Republic,

    he is

    not entitled to

    assert

    the

    identification of Libertas with Civitas. The

    truth

    is,

    of

    course,

    that it

    is

    vrery

    uncertain when the

    tripartition

    was introduced. It does

    not

    yet

    appear in Festus

    (s.v.

    '

    deminutus capite ', p. 6i Lindsay

    --70

    lMfiller),

    and there are some

    passages

    in the Digest

    which

    taken each by

    itself would

    give

    rather the

    impression

    of

    bipartition (D.

    38,

    i6,

    I,

    4; 38,

    i7,

    i8

    50, I3,

    5, 3).

    The tripartitioncertainlydoes not appear n any of the republican

    and

    Augustan passages

    on

    c.d. known to me

    (Cic.,

    Top.

    4

    (i8),

    6

    (29);

    Caes.,

    BC

    2, 32, I0;

    Hor.,

    Carin.

    3,

    5, 42

    ; Livy

    22,

    6o,

    IS).

    It is not

    necessary

    to

    go

    into the modern theories

    on

    c.d., though

    especially

    what has been written

    by

    H.

    Kruger,

    UI.

    Coli

    and F. Desserteaux would

    be

    vrery

    relevrant

    (the most recent discussion

    known to me is between

    R.

    Ambrosino,

    Stuldia

    et

    Documlnz.

    ist. Juris

    6,

    I940, 369, and

    C.

    Gioffredi

    ib.

    II, I945, 30I:

    I

    am in substantial

    agreement

    with the

    latter).

    It seems

    reasonable to

    conclude

    that the

    tripartition

    of

    c.d. was introduced

    in

    the

    early imperial

    age

    and

    does

    not

    affect

    what

    republican

    jurists

    thought

    about Libertas. For

    the

    meaning

    of

    '

    caput

    '

    in

    repu-blican

    texts

    compare

    also

    F. De

    Visscher,

    Le

    re'ginze

    onzain

    de la

    naoxalite'

    947,

    I48.

    I

    may

    perhaps

    add that

    I

    do not

    quite

    agree

    with De

    Visscher

    '

    De

    l'acquisition

    du droit de

    cite

    romain

    par

    l'affranchissernent

    ',

    Studia

    et

    Documniz.

    ist. 7/uris. I2,

    I946, 69.

    One

    of the

    reasons

    for

    my

    disagreement

    is

    to

    be

    found

    in the

    '

    vendere

    trans

    Tiberim',

    but

    I

    cannot

    argue

    the

    point

    here:

    cf. iVM.

    aser,

    Zeitschr. Sav.

    Stift.

    Rom. Abt.

    67, I950, 489,

    n. 59.

    (3) Some of the most famous episodes of the traditional history of Rome are connected with

    Libertas

    (cf.

    U.

    Coli.

    '

    Sul

    parallelismo

    del diritto

    pubblico

    e

    del

    diritto

    privrato

    nel

    periodo

    arcaico

    di

    Roma',

    Stzudia

    et

    Docutnm.

    ,

    1938,

    95). They

    offered an

    explanation

    of

    certain Roman institutions

    and represented a powerful stimulus for remembering and cherishing the formalities of Roman Law.

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.228 on Thu, 12 Jun 2014 17:39:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 (Ok)Resenha Momilgliano

    4/9

    I

    48

    REVIEW

    AND DISCUSSION

    The stories on the origin of provocatio,

    the tale of the

    origins

    of the

    Republic,

    the

    legend

    of Verginia,

    certain episodes of the struggle

    between patricians and plebeians were powerful factors in the

    education of the Romans. These

    traditions may, of course, be said to have already been in existence

    in the second century

    B.C.

    and

    therefore to be outside the chronological limits of

    WV.'s

    esearch.

    But it is evident that some at least of these legends were still being reshaped in the last centuries

    of the Republic and that they

    maintained, and perhaps increased, their educational importance

    during the political struggles

    of the late

    Republic. They

    made it

    possible

    for Cicero to say:

    '

    Aliae

    nationes servitutem pati possunt,

    populi Romani est propria libertas

    '

    (6 Phil.

    i9).

    One is surprised

    to see that

    a

    chapter

    '

    Education

    for Libertas

    '

    is missing

    in

    W.'s book. This is regrettable because

    Roman

    legends

    with

    a

    juridical

    background

    have

    recently been

    the

    object

    of

    lively

    discussion

    among

    French scholars.

    While

    my private opinion

    remains that there is very little in

    Dumezil's

    theories, the studies

    of

    H.

    Levy-Bruhl and P. Noailles

    are

    often

    illuminating. Noailles has, for

    instance, made it

    clearer

    that

    the legend of Verginia as it appears

    in Livy really represents the

    reinterpretation by

    a

    lawyer of

    a much simpler legend. It is interesting to see

    Le'W-Bruhl

    and

    Noailles'

    opinions

    now

    spreading

    in

    Germany (for instance,

    M.

    Kaser,

    l.c.

    474).

    (4) Though

    the

    main

    emphasis

    was

    on juridical Libertas,

    the

    Romans

    in

    the last centuries of

    the

    Republic thought

    of

    Libertas as

    a

    sign

    of

    distinguished

    humanity irrespective of juridical status.

    W. does not seem to have considered this aspect. Unless I am mistaken, he does not quote either

    Ennius' solemn

    words

    in

    a

    tragedy

    (259 R3.

    =

    300 V.2)

    '

    ea libertas

    est, qui pectus purum et firmum

    gestitat

    '

    or

    Terence's

    lines

    '

    feci

    ex

    servo ut esses libertus mihi, propterea quod servibas liberaliter'

    (Andria 37-8,

    on

    which

    cf.

    F.

    Jacoby's suggestive, though probably adventurous, remarks

    in

    Herimes

    44, I909, 362).

    The

    non-juridical approach

    to

    Libertas,

    which

    provided

    M. Antonius

    with

    some

    good

    fun

    (De

    Orat. I, 226),

    became more

    important

    than

    the

    juridical

    when the

    Roman

    Senatorial Republic

    was

    destroyed by

    Caesar.

    Everything

    WV. as written on

    liberty

    in

    the first

    century

    of the Empire is sound and well said.

    A

    word

    on the often misunderstood passage of Tac. Ann.

    I,

    75 would have been useful, but is not

    indispensable.

    The

    comparison

    with

    Professor

    L. Wickert,

    '

    Der

    Prinzipat und die Freiheit,'

    Symbola Coloniensia Iosepho

    Kroll . . . oblata

    II I-I47, is

    favourable to W. Though Wickert quotes

    more

    passages,

    knows

    the

    inscriptions

    and has

    some good remarks,

    his

    conclusion-' jedenfalls ist

    die libertas die der

    Prinzipat

    ertragt und schirmt, nicht mehr die tatige Freiheit des Republikaners,

    sondern die zahme Behaglichkeit des Untertanen' (p.

    I41)-can

    hardly be called a contribution to

    knowledge.

    Yet

    in

    some

    way WV.,oo,

    has missed the full

    implications

    of the fall

    of

    the

    Roman

    Republican

    Government.

    When

    many

    of the

    rights usually

    connected with

    Roman

    Libertas were

    lost,

    some

    people

    rediscovered what

    the

    Greek

    philosophers

    had noticed

    before,

    that

    loss of

    political rights

    involves

    almost

    unexpectedly

    a much more serious offence to

    elementary

    moral

    values.

    PrivTateLaw

    was not

    deeply

    affected. The

    majority

    of

    the Roman

    lawyers

    could

    perhaps go

    on

    working

    without

    noticing any revolutionary

    change:

    E.

    Levy's

    recent

    remarks on this

    subject ('

    Natural

    Law

    in

    Roman

    Thought',

    Stutdia

    et

    Docutmenta

    I5, I949, 22)

    deserve careful

    consideration. But

    people

    more

    directly

    concerned with moral life were

    less

    easy

    to

    placate.

    In

    45-44

    B.C.,

    the

    '

    anni mirabiles

    '

    of Latin

    thought,

    Cicero

    worked

    feverishly

    to

    give

    Rome

    in

    her own

    tongue

    the

    system

    of moral

    and

    metaphysical

    values she

    was still

    lacking,

    '

    ut si

    occupati profuimus aliquid

    civibus nostris

    prosimus etiam,

    si

    possumus,

    otiosi'

    (Tutsc. Disp.

    I,

    3,

    (5)).

    The

    De

    Officiis

    is a code of behaviour

    for the aristocracy just liberated from Caesar s tyranny. During the second big crisis-the Neronian

    one-Seneca

    repeatedly

    faced the

    question

    of the relations between

    personal

    freedom and

    political

    activity;

    Lucan

    (as

    B. Marthi

    observed

    in her

    admirable

    paper

    in A.j.

    Phil.

    66,

    I945, 352)

    showed

    that

    Pompey's

    moral character

    improved

    with

    the

    progress

    of the

    struggle against

    Caesar-'

    seque

    probat

    moriens'

    (viii

    62I);

    and

    Musonius

    explored

    unusual avenues of moral action

    (A.

    C.

    van

    Geytenbeek,

    iMiusoniuis

    utfuts

    n de Griekse

    Diatribe, Amsterdam,

    I948,

    is

    better than

    anything

    else

    on Musonius,

    yet

    insufficient:

    J. Korver,

    '

    Neron

    et

    Musonius,'

    iMinemos.

    V,

    I950, 3I9,

    is

    controversial).

    W. does not

    seem to have

    appreciated

    the

    magnitude

    of the

    Neronian

    crisis: he

    does

    not

    discuss

    either

    Lucan or Musonius

    and

    says

    very

    little about

    Seneca.

    Consequently

    he is not in

    a

    position

    to assess the disillusionment

    of those

    who,

    like

    Helvidius

    Priscus, evidently thought

    that

    Vespasian,

    the friend of Thrasea

    and Barea Soranus

    (Tac.,

    Hist.

    IV,

    7),

    did not come

    up

    to

    expecta-

    tions.

    W.

    attempts

    to reduce

    the

    value of

    the

    passage

    of Dio

    66,

    I2, 2,

    pCaloEiaS

    T?E &?i Kc(T-ryopEi

    icd

    i

    oKpaTiav ETr?IVEI

    without examining the long account of Philostratus, V7ita

    Apoll. Tyan. v,

    33

    ff.,

    about

    the

    discussions

    at the moment of

    Vespasian's

    accession: Philostratus and

    Dio

    have

    at least

    this

    in

    common that

    they

    describe

    people prepared

    to

    question

    the

    very

    foundations of

    the

    Roman principate. There is enough in Tacitus to

    showv

    hat the alternative-Libertas

    or Imperator-

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.228 on Thu, 12 Jun 2014 17:39:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 (Ok)Resenha Momilgliano

    5/9

    REVIEW AND

    DISCUSSION

    I49

    was still

    a

    real

    one in the mind of some persons

    (for instance, Ann.

    i5,

    52,

    4). B. Croce

    found

    Helvidius

    worth

    a

    close

    analysis in

    Qutaderni

    della

    Critica 4,

    I946, 25-35. It

    would

    also have

    been

    important

    to

    take an

    unambiguous

    position about two

    recent interpretations

    of the opposition

    of

    the

    intellectuals. M. A.

    Levi's theory (Nerone e

    i

    sutoi

    tempi I949) that

    Seneca and Lucan

    were

    representatives of a Western ideology against Nero's oriental sympathies can be true only up to

    a point.

    It is not possible to

    combine Lucan's passionate

    interest in Roman

    tradition

    with

    Seneca's

    concern

    for individual perfection.

    The details of

    Levi's theory are

    doubtful:

    for instance, he

    makes

    Barea Soranus

    an accuser of Thrasea

    (p. 205, n. 4) and

    takes kindly to Ciaffi's

    truly fantastic

    attribution

    of the Octavia to

    Annaeus Cornutus (Riv.

    Fil.

    N.S. I5, I937,

    246). In strict

    theory

    there

    is

    more

    to be said for

    Miss J. M. C. Toynbee's

    distinction between

    the Cynic dislike

    of

    the

    emperors

    as

    such and the

    Stoic

    dislike

    of bad emperors

    (Greece and Rome I3, I944,

    43). But

    the facts about

    individual

    philosophers

    do

    not fit

    into this scheme. Helvidius

    Priscus

    who, according

    to

    Miss

    Toynbee,

    went

    Cynic,

    is

    described as Stoic

    by Dio 66,

    I2

    ; and

    it is hardly fair

    to suppose

    that

    Mlusonius

    had evinced 'some unexpected Cynic

    symptoms' when

    he

    was

    exiled by Vespasian.

    WV.

    s far

    more

    persuasive

    on

    the third big crisis-the

    Domitianic one. He sees with

    a clarity

    denied to other

    students of

    Tacitus,

    but

    not

    to the

    great Tacitist, Amelot

    de la Houssaie, that

    Tacitus

    analysed

    the conflict between

    Libertas and

    '

    adulatio

    '. W., however,

    does not go into the

    conflict

    between Libertas and imperialism from whose difficulties Tacitus never disentangled himself.

    Moreover,

    if

    Tacitus

    is the first to make '

    adulatio

    ' the centre of his analysis of tyranny, the problem

    of

    freedom

    of

    speech

    inevitably

    concerned most

    of

    the writers

    of the imperial age

    from Phaedrus

    and Persius

    to Quintilian

    and Juvenal. Precisely

    because Libertas was

    no longer a clear juridical

    concept, these

    writers

    are not

    concerned

    with

    formal rights to speak

    in assemblies, but with

    the

    opposite

    of

    '

    adulatio

    '.

    The study

    of freedom

    of

    speech

    under the

    Principate

    is not to

    be

    found

    in W.'s book.

    (5)

    It

    is

    an

    open question

    whether we must introduce

    Greek texts

    in

    a

    discussion

    on Libertas.

    As long

    as Libertas represents

    the rights of the

    Romans as rulers, the

    investigation

    must remain

    strictly

    confined

    to Roman citizens.

    But I

    do

    not see

    how

    one could

    separate

    the

    discussion

    on

    Libertas

    from that on

    Eleutheria when

    one

    comes

    to the imperial age.

    Many of the people

    who

    wrote

    in

    Greek

    were

    by

    now

    Roman

    citizens,

    and

    in

    any case

    both Roman citizens and provincials

    obeyed

    the

    emperor.

    In

    practice

    W.

    admits

    Dio,

    on whom

    he

    follows

    von Arnim (discussed

    below),

    but not Philo, Pluitarch, an-d Epictetus. Mtiisonius is mentioned, but his writings are not examined-

    a

    clear

    '

    reductio

    ad absurdum'

    of the

    distinction.

    Nothing is better

    than Plutarch's Precepts

    of

    Statecraft

    about

    liberty

    in

    Greece

    under the Romans. Plutarch

    exactly

    defines the limits of

    political

    activity

    for an ambitious young

    Greek,

    he

    warns

    the officers of the

    city not to urge foolishly

    the

    people

    to imitate

    the actions and

    ideals of

    theii

    ancestors,

    and

    he

    invites

    them to remember

    that

    they

    have the boots of

    the

    Roman

    soldiers over

    their head. But

    he is also

    perfectly

    candid about

    his way of understanding

    freedom of discussion.

    It would

    be bad for the leaders to give

    the

    impression

    that

    they

    constantly agree among

    themselves.

    They

    should

    make some

    show of

    disagreement

    (8I3

    B).

    This notion of

    freedom of

    speech

    is also

    a

    key

    to

    the

    understanding

    of Dio.

    Any

    Greek speaker

    had to

    rediscover

    for

    himself

    the

    narrow

    path

    existing

    between the

    suspicions

    of the

    Roman

    authorities and the

    passions

    of the Greek

    crowds. So to Dio

    we can turn.

    II. Dio

    of

    Prutsa,

    the

    Rhodiana

    libertas'

    and

    the

    Philosophers.-i.

    Introduction.-Synesius

    of

    Cyrene, dissenting from Philostratus, divided Dio of Prusa's literary activities into a sophistic and a

    philosophic period

    (Dio

    35A,

    p.

    233 Terzaghi). Synesius,

    admittedly,

    had a

    personal

    interest

    in

    shoiw-

    ing

    that Dio

    was

    ultimately

    able

    to

    combine

    good philosophy

    with

    good

    Greek

    (see

    his letter to

    Hypatia,

    no.

    I54

    in

    Hercher, Epistol.

    Graeci ed.

    Didot, p.

    735).

    His

    views

    were

    accepted

    and

    developed by

    H. von

    Arnim

    (i898)

    who classified

    Dio's

    works

    into three

    groups: sophistic speeches

    and

    essays

    before the

    exile

    (which

    he dated

    in A.D.

    82)

    ;

    essays

    written

    during

    the exile

    but

    subsequent

    to his

    conversion

    to

    philosophy;

    literary

    and

    philosophic

    production

    later

    than

    his recall

    from exile

    (96-I20

    ?).

    According

    to von

    Arnim,

    Dio,

    after

    having

    been

    a virtuoso in

    his

    youth

    and a

    philosophic

    rebel

    in his

    maturity,

    subsequently

    discovered

    the

    possibility

    of

    bringing

    eloquence

    into

    harmony

    with

    philosophy.

    Von

    Arnim's

    sympathetic description

    of

    Dio

    contributed

    much to an

    understanding

    of

    the

    first-century philosophers.

    But doubts

    have

    repeatedly

    been

    expressed

    about the

    rigidity

    of his

    chronological

    scheme.

    Indeed,

    as a Russian critic

    rightly

    observed

    (V.

    E.

    Valdenberg,

    '

    The

    Political Philosophy of Dio Chrysostom,' in Izvestia Akad. Navk SSSK

    I926,

    p.

    946 (in Russian),

    but

    see also

    R.

    Hirzel,

    Der

    Dialog

    II, 85,

    n.

    3),

    von Arnim

    treated Dio's

    life

    as if it were

    a

    Hegelian

    triad:

    rhetoric-thesis

    ; philosophy-antithesis

    ;

    final

    period

    of

    harmony

    between

    rhetoric

    and

    philosophy-synthesis.

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.228 on Thu, 12 Jun 2014 17:39:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 (Ok)Resenha Momilgliano

    6/9

    I50

    REVIEW

    AND DISCUSSION

    Nobody, however,

    seems

    to

    have re-examined the evidence in detail. The

    following

    discussion

    is confined to one speech, but

    it is meant to show

    that

    von Arnim's account of the intellectual

    development of Dio is founded upon

    a chronology

    of his

    works which is insufficiently supported

    by the evidence.

    2.

    Dio and the statutsof Rhodes.-Dio's speech to the Rhodians (xxxi) was written after Nero's

    death

    (prg.

    I48)

    and describes

    Rhodes'

    status as that of a civitas

    libera (II2

    TnV EAUEVpiaV O'iEUeE

    aTropacAEiv

    ;).

    But Rhodes lost her freedom

    during Vespasian's reign, and probably in

    the first

    years of it. Thus, one would naturally

    date the

    speech betwseen

    A.D. 68

    and, say,

    c.

    73. Von

    Arnim,

    however, did not accept this date, because it appeared

    to him

    incompatible with wvhat

    he knew

    about the progress of Dio's mind.

    He took the

    speech

    to

    be indicative of

    an intermediate

    stage

    in Dio's ascension from rhetoric to philosophy

    and

    suggested

    that a

    date about

    A.D.

    8o would be

    more suitable to

    it than

    a date

    about A.D.

    70.

    His

    theory

    involved the

    assumption that Rhodes

    recovered her freedom before the alleged date

    of Dio's exile,

    A.D.

    82. But von Arnim, who did not

    hesitate to make this

    assumption, thought

    he had found some corroborative

    evidence in

    IG

    xii,

    i,

    58,

    a

    Rhodian inscription

    in

    honour

    of a man who

    as a

    Prytanis conveyed the expressions of the

    EVo 1a

    and

    -rriuTis

    of

    his

    island to Titus.

    Von

    Arnim

    agreed

    that the

    terminology of this inscription (closely

    paralleled by Dio xxxi,

    II3)

    seemed

    '

    nicht

    auf ein Unterthanenverhaltnis, sondern nur auf das alte

    Bundesverhaltnis zu passen' (p.

    2I7).

    His conclusion was that Rhodes received back her freedom

    and that

    Dio wvrote

    his

    speech (xxxi)

    in the same

    years

    between

    79

    and 8i.

    Von Arnim persuaded

    A.

    Wilhelm

    to

    accept

    his

    dating

    with

    consequences

    which

    became

    apparent

    in I9I3

    when the great

    Viennese master

    gave

    his

    opinion

    on the

    inscription

    first

    published

    in

    'Eriji.

    'ApX.

    I9II, 59

    (now

    Dittenberger,

    S11.3

    8i9).

    The new

    inscription

    honours Domitian and alludes to a

    grant

    of freedom:

    the most natural interpretation

    of it is that the freedom

    w-as

    granted by Domitian. Wilhelm, however,

    suggested that the grant had already

    been made by Titus. He also quoted Plutarch., Praec. gel'. r'eip.

    8I5

    d,

    as

    evidence for

    a later anti-Rhodian phase

    of Domitian

    (Sitz.

    Wien.

    Akad.

    I75, I9I3,

    50).

    On

    the other

    hand,

    Hiller

    von

    Gaertringen,

    who

    incidentally

    seems

    to

    have misunderstood

    what

    Wilhelm said, took the view that

    Domitian

    first

    deprived

    the

    Rhodians of their freedom and then

    gave it back to them (P-INV .v. Rhodos,

    Suppl. v,

    8ii

    f.). Hiller's scheme can be sumrnarized

    as follows:-

    about

    A.D.

    71, Rhodes

    loses her

    liberty;

    A.D.

    79-81, Rhodes recovers her liberty: Dio writes Or.

    xxxi;

    after

    A.D. 8i, Rhodes

    again

    loses her

    liberty;

    before

    A.D.

    96,

    Rhodes

    recovers her

    liberty.

    It

    is

    now

    time

    to

    quote

    the texts

    and

    comment

    on them

    (i)

    Tac.,

    Ann.

    XII,

    58

    (A.D.

    53).

    reddita Rhodiis

    libertas, adempta saepe

    aut

    firmata, prout

    bellis

    externis meruerant aut domi

    seditione

    deliquerant.

    (2)

    Suet.,

    Vesp.

    8.

    Achaiam, Lyciam,

    Rhodum, Byzantium,

    Samum libertate

    adempta,

    item

    Trachiam

    Ciliciam

    et

    Commagenem

    dicionis

    regiae usque

    ad id

    tempus

    in

    provinciarum

    formam

    redegit. Cappadociae propter

    adsiduos

    barbarorum incursus

    legiones

    addidit

    consularemque

    rectorem

    imposuit pro eq.

    R.

    (3)

    Hieron.

    Chion.

    p.

    i88 Helm

    (A.D.

    74).

    Achaia

    Lycia

    Rhodus

    Byzantium

    Samus Thracia

    Cilicia

    Commagene quae

    liberae

    antea et

    sub

    regibus

    amicis

    erant

    in

    provincias

    redactae.

    (4) Sextus Rufius, Brev.

    io.

    Sub Vespasiano principe insularum provincia facta est.

    (5) IG

    xii, I, 58. 'Ep,ay6pav

    0aiviiTriTov

    KXa&oiov

    TaTVTa

    TpaVQavTa

    KaQl

    uvvPovuAEJvaVTa

    T

    co

    6a'pcp

    -a

    7uv9povprTa

    Ta-

    -TaTpiEl

    {T&-

    E'V

    TC^)

    TaS

    lTpUvTaVEiaS

    XPOVCX)

    Kai

    lia6ElIaXEVOV

    a

    &E'X

    EX

    a

    -ForriS

    To

    rl'

    T?

    ThOV

    aJTOKpaTopa

    TiTov

    CPaoiniov

    Kaicapa

    EEpaaCTov

    OiVEcruacyiavOv

    Kai Tov

    cviiYTavTa oIKOV auTou Kai Tav IEpOV COYVKM1TOV

    KaC TOV

    Ma,uOv

    TOV PcoaiCOV EUYvoiaV Kai TTicYTiv

    Kai

    TUXOvTa

    TCY)V KaAiUCTCov

    ypaQIa4rTcov

    arTo

    TOU

    eEOl

    EEpacrTOU

    ?V

    Trc-

    TraS

    rpUTvYaVEiaS

    Kailpo

    KTA.

    (6) Dittenberger, Syll.3,

    8i9

    [DomZlitiano].

    Kai

    AoPETi'a

    E)E

    EEPacTr

    'Opovoi

    'Iaccov

    'Ap1CTOyVEVUS

    BouA[i((6as)]

    ayTCapEVOS

    ?-rr. XEpO[Va&]aOu Kail

    EvXpas,

    Eq)

    oU a&?E[Ka]TEaTaxeTl

    a

    TVaXTpios

    1TOAErrEfa(s>,

    Kai

    0o Mios

    6o

    E\OucYavouvTiCOV

    KTA.

    (7)

    Plutarch.,

    Pr-aec.

    ger. reip. 815

    d.

    aAopEv'

    6E

    Kal KYV6VYEUOlCYO1

    01eEYV,

    C'OTFE7p

    yKUpaV

    iEpaV apa,EYOV

    E

    auTo

    1

    iv

    rappY)iQY

    ETFi

    TOIS

    1EyfaTOIS-

    O1Q

    fpyop1aouS ?ri

    N?poVOS

    KTEAa3E

    TTpacypaTa

    KCi

    'Po8iouvS

    E'YyKOS ?TF AopETlaVOU.

    About

    (i)

    it

    will

    be

    enough

    to

    say

    that it

    refers

    only

    to the

    period

    before A.D.

    53.

    I

    doubt

    the

    wisdom of

    pressing

    the

    meaning

    of

    '

    saepe

    ',

    but

    anyone

    wlho

    wishes to follow van

    Gelder

    and

    state

    ' also nicht

    zwreimal,

    sondern saepe st den

    Rhodiern die Freiheit entzogen

    w7orden

    (Geschichte der

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.228 on Thu, 12 Jun 2014 17:39:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 (Ok)Resenha Momilgliano

    7/9

    REVIEW AND DISCUSSION

    I5

    I

    alten

    Rhodier

    I900, 175),

    will have to

    search the history of Rhodes to find a grant

    of freedom before

    A.D.

    53, which is beyond

    our present purpose.

    Suetonius in (z)

    certainly implies that Vespasian acted in

    the first years of his reign, but

    St.

    Jerome

    (3)

    does not help to date

    Suetonius's passage more precisely. One or

    twvoof the changes

    mentioned by Suetonius may have been dated in 74 by some other writer known to St. Jerome.

    In

    A.D.

    77 Pliny the Elder had not yet

    registered one of the facts recorded by

    Suetonius, the change

    of

    status of

    Byzantium (NH IV, 46).

    (4)

    is frankly

    mysterious but does not affect our

    question (see, for instance, J. Marquardt,

    RZumn.taatsverw.2

    I,

    348).

    (5)

    does not say, as

    von Arnim and his followvers imply,

    that Titus granted freedom to

    Rhodes.

    Nobody indeed can know

    wlhat

    the

    Ka

    -ra

    palUua-ra

    T

    were meant to convey.

    But it is arguable

    that

    a

    grant of freedom was a thing to be

    mentioned

    explicitly as we see in Ditt.,

    Syll.3 819,

    or in

    IG

    XII, I, 2.

    (5)

    if anything rather

    discourages the notion

    that Titus restored freedom to

    the

    Rhodians. As for von

    Arnim's remark that

    ElJvola

    and

    -TriasTi

    suit a free city better than a provincial

    towvn,

    it is

    easy to answver

    hat

    Rhodes wvas

    probably proud

    enough not to change her terminology

    according to her fortunes and

    misfortunes under the emperors. What

    may have happened is that

    Titus

    promised freedom by

    his

    Ka'?OaTa

    ypappara

    but

    did

    not live long enough to fulfil the

    promise.

    In

    that case Domitian would simply

    have fulfilled his brother's promise.

    (6) prima facie shoows

    that Rhodes

    recovered her freedom under Domitian (on

    TrarTplos

    TroAlTfa

    cf.

    IG xii,

    I, 2,

    1. 12-13 [aTrroo0eEia]as

    Tr

    7T0oXE

    QS 1TaTpToU

    TFoATTEaS

    Kal TCOX)6vv

    pc

    -v

    ToX)

    [.v

    with

    reference to Claudius's grant.

    (7)

    does not say that Rhodes lost her

    freedom under Domitian, nor does it

    seem to imply any

    change of status. Plutarch

    seems to say that the wvisemen of

    Rhodes managed to extricate themselves

    from a difficult

    situation. There is no reason to believe that

    Plutarch refers to a date earlier than (6),

    though

    if

    he

    did,

    it would

    not prove

    anything.

    The

    conclusion of this

    analysis

    is

    that, according

    to

    the

    best

    of

    our

    evidence,

    Rhodes lost

    her

    freedom in the early

    years of Vespasian's reign and recovered

    it some time under

    Domitian.

    To

    anyone

    who

    has

    no

    preconceived

    ideas on Dio's

    evolution

    this

    means

    that

    Dio

    may

    have

    written

    his speech

    either between Nero's death

    and

    Vespasian's move

    against

    Rhodes or after

    Domitian's act of liberation. Three further arguments may perhaps narrow these chronological

    limits.

    I

    write them in order of

    decreasing cogency

    (a)

    Or. xxxi

    was written wlhen

    the details

    of

    Nero's

    reign

    were fresh in men's memories. A date

    after

    Dio's return from exile

    (A.D. 96)

    is

    unlikely.

    (b)

    It seems common sense to

    suggest that

    Dio could

    hardly

    have

    written Or.

    xxxi

    during

    his

    exile. The date of the

    beginning

    of

    his

    exile

    depends,

    according

    to the most

    probable theory,

    on

    the

    date of the death of T. Flavius

    Sabinus,

    which is

    rightly put

    between

    82

    and

    89 (A. Stein,

    P-WV

    .v. Flavius

    vi,

    2615;

    PIR2, F

    355).

    This would exclude

    at

    least the

    years 89-96.

    (c)

    Dio

    does not seem to be

    addressing people who

    have

    recovered their freedom

    only

    a few

    years

    earlier. WIhat he

    says

    in

    xxxi,

    112-113

    applies

    better

    perhaps

    to

    the

    period

    of

    Vespasian (before

    the

    punishment

    of

    Rhodes)

    than to the

    period

    of Domitian

    (after

    the

    repeal

    of

    Vespasian's act).

    Anyway,

    the

    evidence

    so far

    known seems

    to

    point

    to the

    following

    conclusions: about

    71-5

    Vespasian deprives

    Rhodes of the

    status

    of civitas libera

    (andfoederata);

    after

    8i

    Domitian restores

    her liberty; Dio xxxi was written either between 8i and 89

    (wl-hich

    would imply that Domitian

    granted freedom some

    time before 89) or more probably

    between

    69

    and

    c.

    75.

    The

    only

    date

    which seems to be

    really unlikely

    for

    Or.

    XXXI

    S

    79-8I,

    the date

    suggested by

    von Arnim.

    3.

    Dio

    and the

    Philosophzers.-The

    results so

    far

    obtained

    encourage

    us to re-examine

    the

    problem of the relations between Dio and the

    philosophers

    before his exile.

    Speech

    XXXI

    contains

    a

    very favourable allusion to a

    philosopher-distinguished by

    Roman

    citizenship

    and

    high

    birth-

    wlho

    reproached

    the Athenians for

    taking pleasure

    in

    gladiatorial

    shows

    122.

    Kail TOV

    ElT?rovTa

    TrEpi

    TOUJTOU iAaCOpOV

    Kai

    vOueE-TlbcyavTa

    aTous

    OVKUaTK

    TE?awVTo O18?E

    ETF)VEcyav,

    a

    OUTCA)

    E?U Epavav,

    C07TE

    EKE?1VOV pEV

    ovTa

    yEVEl PcoCi0v

    I8?VO;

    UCTEpOV,

    sotcv

    8E

    T

    lKc[aJT1)V

    EXOVTc

    1)AlK1qS

    O18?i5

    EK

    'TTaXVu

    7TToAAOu

    TETUXTIKEV,

    0OPOOyOip?VqOV

    8E

    p6vov paclcTa

    PETa

    TOv1

    apXaiovS

    aK&KOAOU0e

    PEPICOKEVai

    TOTs

    AOyOi,

    KQTcOTa-Ta

    V

    fT V'vO6IV

    Kai

    pacSov

    E'?CEae

    8laTp43Elv

    a00aXOcUE

    S

    'EA0axoS.

    Reasonably enough,

    this has been taken as

    a

    reference to Musonius

    Rufus,

    a

    knight

    of

    Etruscan

    origin (Tac.,

    Ann.

    14, 59;

    Hist.

    3, 8I).

    What matters most

    is

    that

    Dio must

    haTve

    written

    this

    passage at a moment in

    which

    3e

    was

    friendly

    to at

    least one philosopher and

    did not think

    it

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.228 on Thu, 12 Jun 2014 17:39:40 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/17/2019 (Ok)Resenha Momilgliano

    8/9

    I52

    REVIEW

    AND DISCUSSION

    dangerous to exhibit

    his friendship

    in public. Other evidence

    suggests

    that before his

    exile Dio

    was

    not always

    of one mind about

    philosophers. Here

    are the

    relevant

    passages:-

    (i) Fronto,

    p.

    II5

    Naber=

    II,

    p.

    50

    Haines (Loeb).

    Quid nostra

    memoria Euphrates,

    Dio,

    Timocrates, Athenodotus

    ? Quid

    horum magister Musonius

    ?

    (2) Philostr.

    Vita Apoll. Tyan.

    V, 27. OivcT-raciavoU 8?ET7V aUTOKpaTOpa

    apX7(lV

    TVEplVOOUVTOS

    T?pi

    Ta

    oT,opa

    Ti;

    AiyuTFrTC(

    EV,

    E

    I

    1TpOXCOPOvJTOS

    ETi

    TflV AyuvTTov,

    ACOVES pEV

    KQI EvppaTal

    ...

    XalpEIV TFapcEKEEUOVTO 'ATro.AAOcvioS

    8?

    TTapaTrAflai@cS

    pEv

    Eupp'Tn

    Kai

    AfCoVI

    ?TEpi

    TO'TCV

    EXQIPE. V,

    31,

    CZ

    pc(1AEU, ElTrEV

    (Apollonius),

    Ev)pp'Trns

    Kai

    Aicov

    ra'ac col yvc'puioi

    ovTEs

    TTpO?S

    elJpalS

    EiCiV.

    Cf.

    also V, 37-8.

    (3)

    Th-emist. or.

    x

    de pace p.

    I65 Dindorf

    (I39

    a). 7V TIS Trri TCAV 'rrpOyOVCoV

    TCV

    7T1[ETEPCOV

    uT1KTrlS

    v71p,

    MEAayKouaS

    ovopa

    auTco,

    Ka'AlCTOS

    TE

    Kai

    pEy1acTOS

    Kai

    TT,V TEXVYnV

    EU8OKIcoTaToS,

    Ou

    Kai Tov

    TiTov

    qpacyiv

    EpacyTrlv

    yEvEcyeal

    Tov a(TOKpaTopaX

    (4)

    Synesius,

    Dio 37 A.

    a'

    ol'ToS

    y?E

    TF1Ta 8iT Kaci

    paTcrra

    COCYTc)V

    Els

    'p1OCYOaOUS

    TE

    Kai

    piosaoqpiav

    aQTrfvalCYXuVTflKEV. aTE

    yap,

    oipal,

    qpuc7cOS

    ?Xcv

    XoucaX;

    i

    Kai

    To

    p7fTOpEUE1V

    aUTO flleEuEv,

    aEpVOv

    aQVaQTETFE1cEVOs

    Eival

    TOU V KaTa'

    1ioapiav

    TO V KaTa

    T'S

    KO1VQ

    U1TO?VIEIs

    QeE)V O

    TE

    KaTa

    TcoV

    pI1OaCY6qov

    a

    AT6yo;

    ?ai-rouv&aeCq

    cy6cpa a-MyXcoviapvos

    Kl

    v

    cUxpa 6'KV7ac- K Td O

    rp's

    MoUck

    viov

    E-TEpOS TOiOOTOS,

    oU

    ppOvyUaCopovoU TC

    TOTrcA) ToJ

    AicovoS,

    a' ?K l1ae'?Co;

    ypC9OVTO

    ...

    38 A

    ouTCs

    yap av

    ElWPEV TOUS

    TE

    qIAocooUs

    Kai

    Tovs

    a'To

    ToJTo

    CYOPlCYTlKOUS A6yoUS

    liE1kpoTES EKaTEpOUs

    Xcopi

    aS

    X C

    EUTVp ?V

    VuKTO,uaXia,

    TrEp1TEVu6,Eea aQuTC, vuv

    JEV

    paOVT1

    2ZCAKpaTq

    Kaci

    ZflVvcva

    TOYS

    EK AIOVUoiCOV

    CYK

    opuiacyl

    Kai

    Tovs

    aTr'

    au(Tcov

    aOl

    vT1

    TacYfl

    E

    avQUVEUl

    YfS

    Ka'

    ea

  • 8/17/2019 (Ok)Resenha Momilgliano

    9/9

    REVIEW AND

    DISCUSSION

    153

    Such being

    the evidence,

    we

    must see

    hoow

    Dio Or.

    XXxI,

    iz2,

    can best be harmonized

    with the

    other texts.

    If Dio's general attack against

    the philosophers

    (as distinguished

    from the

    -rpo6s

    Moacuw,viov)

    ither

    was

    written

    some years after

    71

    or made an emphatic

    exception

    for

    Mlusonius,

    I

    do not see

    why

    xxxi,

    I22

    could not refer

    to Musonius

    and have been

    written about 70-5. On

    the

    other hand, if it is felt that Dio must haTveattacked the philosophers in

    7I

    and that

    his

    attack is

    incompatible with the trend

    of

    xxxi, 122-3

    we

    must put

    xxxi

    in the early years

    of

    Domitian

    and

    have it as an implicit recantation

    of his former attack against the

    philosophers (and possibly

    of

    his

    animadversions on

    Mlusonius).

    As far as I can see, there is not

    evidence enough to enable us

    to

    choose. But

    an early date for

    xxxi

    is

    consistent

    with

    what

    we

    know

    about the early connections

    of

    Dio with Musonius

    and

    Euphrates.

    This date

    also makes it unnecessary to suppose

    that Dio

    in

    xxxi

    withdrew1

    his

    attack against the philosophers (or

    more specifically his remarks

    on

    Musonius,

    if

    the

    allusion in

    122

    iS

    taken to refer to

    him).

    I

    like

    to think that

    Or. xxxi

    was

    written

    before

    the

    attack

    against the

    philosophers and to imagine that

    the

    -rpo6sMouvcoviovwas

    an address

    (or

    a

    reply)

    to

    Musonius composed when

    it became apparent

    that he had lost Vespasian's

    favour.

    4.

    Dio

    and the

    '

    libertas'

    of the Greeks.-Dio's speech to

    the Rhodians is so

    long

    and so full

    of

    sophistry

    that one is easily inclined to underrate

    its

    positive

    quality.

    By giving

    new

    names to

    old

    statues so

    as to honour contemporaries in the

    cheapest

    way,

    the Rhodians were first

    of all

    guilty

    of meanness-w hich any well-bred Hellene would know how to classify. But they were also guilty

    of

    adulation for the Romans

    because, obviously enough, many of the ne

    w

    labels were

    put up

    to

    please the Roman

    authorities. Dio is well

    aware

    of this implication. His

    argument

    is that

    the

    Rhodians ought not to try to

    preserve the status of a ci?vitas ibera

    (and foederata) by practices

    which

    stultify any pretence of

    freedom.

    The honour of Hellas is in

    question

    (157). Because

    Rhodes has

    no

    longer any

    possibility of political leadership,

    she must defend

    her dignity (I62-3).

    It

    is

    better

    to

    become a

    slave

    (8o0AElEIV

    UpJv

    -r65

    Trav-rTi

    EA-\Tov

    fi&r)

    than

    to

    live

    in

    a

    precarious

    and

    undignified

    liber-tas (i

    u).

    Dio, apart from being loquacious

    and

    over-subtle,

    must needs

    appeal to the rivalries between

    Greeks

    (in this

    case especially to the

    rivalry

    between

    Rhodes and Athens). But by putting

    dignity

    of

    behaviour

    before the juridical status of a civitas

    libera,

    Dio was saying something

    essenitial.

    He

    was,

    in

    fact, doing something

    comparable with what certain

    Roman

    senators

    and

    knights,

    his

    contemporaries,

    were doing

    when

    theY

    refused

    to pay for their privileges by undignified

    behaviour-

    'adulatio '. He was saying that the status of a civitas liber-a s not worth saving if it must be defended

    by constant use of

    '

    adulatio

    '. The allusion to the Roman philosopher

    shows

    that it was far

    from

    Dio's

    intention to antagonize

    the

    Romans.

    He

    presented a Roman philosopher

    as a

    model

    to the

    Greeks

    (cf.

    also the remark of prg.

    iii).

    If he wrote

    in the years

    in which

    Vespasian reconsidered

    the

    grant of

    libertas

    made by Nero to provincial

    Greece, there

    woould be even more point in

    his

    discussion.

    Few

    or

    none of Dio's other

    speeches provide lessons of

    this kind. One of the

    reasolns

    is that

    Dio

    himself waasnot independent of the Romans

    and had to seek

    their

    help

    when there were

    economic

    and

    social difficulties

    in his own

    town.

    Or.

    XLVI,

    another pre-exilic speech,

    is a very good

    example

    of this

    dependence.

    As Dio puts it objectively

    ouJ

    y'ap

    A(XVe0a(VE1

    TCAJvEv

    Tacs

    TroAEoIV

    OOJE?V

    TrotVS

    T1YE[JOVas

    -

    MyCo

    5? TO1'S EI'iOUS

    r)YEPoVC(S

    TCAJv

    EXveae&

    -

    '

    ScJTrEp TCJ)V

    Trail5iCoV

    TCJ)v a'TaK-rTOTEpCA)V

    IKOI -TpOS TOUV l1cXaKcX?\OU&

    KaXT1yOpOJIJiV

    01

    1TpoJr)KoVrE5,

    ouTCA0JI

    Kal

    Ta

    TCV

    5T1CV

    aXapTTaTa

    TrpOS

    EKEiVOUS

    aTrayyE?AETcra

    (14).

    ARNALDO

    MONIIGLIANO.

    This content downloaded from 195 34 79 228 on Thu 12 Jun 2014 17:39:40 PM

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp