1 oki. el rostro humano de la temprana europa de la edad moderna. cfr quevedo grotesco retrato...

Upload: papelerito

Post on 04-Jun-2018

216 views

Category:

Documents


0 download

TRANSCRIPT

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    1/15

    ANGELAKIjournal of the theoretical humanitiesvolume 16 number 1 march 2011

    In an anonymous 1598 translation of AristotlesPolitics we read that Nature who hathbestowed the power of Speech vpon man,

    maketh nothing in vaine.1 Perhaps more

    recognizable in its modern rendition, man is

    the only animal whom [nature] has endowed with

    the gift of speech,2 this is an idea that has

    haunted Western philosophy since the fourth

    century BCE. It is a conception of difference

    perhaps even the conception of difference that

    continues to do two inseparable things: to

    construct the human as the only meaning-

    making species, and to relegate animals to a

    place of silence. This is a silence based on their

    perceived inability to speak, and it is also a

    silence based on humanitys unwillingness to

    speak fully about and for them. Indeed, writing at

    the end of the twentieth century Jacques Derrida

    noted that the animal as a being with a capacityfor a response and not just a reaction is

    something that philosophy perhaps forgets,

    perhaps being this calculated forgetting itself.3

    It is not just speech that is at stake in

    Aristotles statement. There are other issues

    that go with his claim about humanitys unique

    status that are sometimes forgotten, or rather are

    subsumed under a concentration on spoken

    language. He continues (again, quoting from the

    1598 translation):

    Voice which is the signifier of ioy and sadnes,

    is bestowed for this cause vpon other creatures,

    for euen Nature proceedeth so farre in them,

    that shee giueth them a feeling of ioy and

    griefe, and a power to declare the same to

    others. But Speech is giuen vnto vs to signifie

    what is profitable and what vnprofitable, and

    consequently what is iust and what vniust.

    For this is a proprietie belonging vnto man

    aboue all other liuing creatures, that he onely

    hath a sense and feeling of good and euill,

    and of iust and vniust. The communion of

    which things begetteth and establisheth a

    house and a Cittie.4

    The distinction of voice and speech, then, is to be

    read as a manifestation of another, precedingdifference. An animal, for Aristotle, cannot be

    just or unjust because such conceptions require

    access to a realm of abstraction that is not

    available to the animal mind, a mind which is

    capable only of reacting to and thus of giving

    voice to immediate circumstances. In this

    worldview, a plant has a vegetative soul that

    allows for growth, nutrition and reproduction;

    an animal has a vegetative and a sensitive soul,

    which allows for movement and sensory engage-

    ment with the physical world; a human has a

    erica fudge

    THE HUMAN FACE OF

    EARLY MODERNENGLAND

    ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/11/010097^14 2011 Taylor & Francis

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    2/15

    vegetative, a sensitive and a rational soul that is

    immortal and gives access to the abstract.5

    Because of its limitation to the sensual world,

    an animal cannot be said therefore to live socially,

    for social living must be underpinned by, for

    example, an agreed set of ethical (i.e., abstract)rules. Following this train of thought into the

    early modern period my focus in this essay

    Sir Francis Bacon wrote in 1625 that whosoever

    in the frame of his nature and affections is unfit

    for friendship, he taketh it of the beast, and not

    from humanity.6 To be alone to live outside

    of society is to be not human.

    But it was not only that animals were believed

    to be outside of the realm of the social in this

    period. They were also not constituted asindividuals. Alongside abstract knowledge ani-

    mals were believed to lack self-knowledge, some-

    thing vital for both individual and social being.

    Sir Miles Sandys, writing in 1634, asked a series

    of questions with a clear answer:

    Doth the horse know that he is a horse, or, that

    he is a beast, and thou a man? . . . or doth the

    Dogge (which of all beasts is mans chiefe

    attendant) know, whether thou art a man,

    or a beast? no certainely. . . . onely man knowesthat hee is man.7

    Two decades later, the Hertfordshire physician

    John Bulwer, whose work is central to this essay,

    wrote that men descending into themselves may

    know themselves to be men and not beasts, and

    learne to order this August Domicil of man

    reverently to the health of the Body, and the

    honour of the Soule.8 Self-knowledge is avail-

    able only to humans, and like abstract knowl-

    edge allows for social living. Having access to

    the abstract notion the human, and knowing

    who one is oneself and whether the other is a

    human or a beast, sits at the foundation of a

    society. So a dog can only ever be an attendant;

    it can be made to serve humanity but can never

    be a full member of the human community.

    In this essay I look at a number of writings

    from the first half of the seventeenth century

    and trace out the ways in which this argument

    of exclusion circulates. The materials used here

    form a particular discourse on animals which

    Aristotles ideas. An alternative early modern

    point of view will be explored elsewhere. In this

    essay, moving out from questions of language

    and communication, I explore how these early

    seventeenth-century discussions of sociality and

    individuality take up the body as well as the

    mind. The possession of a face is at the centre

    of these debates. Indeed, in this period called

    both the Renaissance and the early modern,

    where ancient past and contemporary present

    are entangled, discussions about faces are always

    discussions about being human.

    meaningful bodies

    It is not only animals that have been relegatedby their lack of speech. In ancient Greece, for

    example, human deafness was linked to muteness

    which, in turn, was understood to go hand-in-

    hand with an inability to reason.9 Once again,

    this conception was followed by later writers,

    and in his 1648 Philocophus: Or, The Deafe and

    Dumbe Mans FriendJohn Bulwer noted:

    The condition that they are in who are borne

    deafe and dumbe, is indeed very sad and

    lamentable: for they are looked upon as

    misprisions of nature, and wanting speech,

    are reckoned little better then Dumbe

    Animals, that want words to expresse their

    conceptions; and men that have lost the

    Magna Charta of speech and priviledge of

    communication, and society with men.

    Bulwer thus repeats Aristotles distinction of

    human from animal as being about speech and

    society (and it becomes clear that animal as a

    category here includes the less-than-human

    human), and he notes in the following pages the

    status of the deaf in Foro Civili as being one

    of exclusion. Legally, deaf people are without

    rights because without expression: they cannot

    be witnesses, cannot draw up wills.10 But Bulwer

    is challenging this Aristotelian conception.

    He suggests that a deaf person might learn lip

    reading, or ocular audition as he terms it, and

    so have language and therefore enter the social

    world.11 Thus Bulwer argues that communication

    might be possible in ways other than speech: that

    early modern england

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    3/15

    the interpretation of lip motion but in the form

    of gesture which is, he states, the universall

    language of Humane nature.12

    The signifying body that comes to the fore

    in Philocophus is of constant interest to

    Bulwer. Whether he is worrying about facial

    musculature in Pathomyotomia (1649 a text

    to which I return), or body modification

    (tattoos, scarification, the use of make-up) in

    Anthropometamorphosis (1650, enlarged 1653),

    the eloquence of the human body is central.

    Indeed, his first work, published in 1644, is a

    study of gestural language. This book is made

    up of two texts, Chirologia and Chironomia

    (the natural language of the hand and the rule

    of the hand respectively13). The first tracesthe signification of individual hand gestures in

    classical texts as a way of establishing a lexicon

    of natural, universal hand language, while the

    second looks at the cultural refinements of this

    natural language. For Bulwer, in gestural lan-

    guage the individual can truly express themselves

    and thus be truly human. Indeed, he states that

    he will handle gesture, as the only speech and

    general language of human nature.14

    Thus, in arguing for a universal language andin tracing classical precedent, Bulwer establishes

    what he regards as a trans-cultural and trans-

    historical human nature, and a new way of

    marking out what makes the human a human.15

    Of the handshake, for example, he writes:

    Our ancestors also had this expression of

    hospitable love in a real respect when they

    knew no greater term of reproach than to call

    a man unhospitable. This expression of the

    hand continues in force and estimation andbears such sway among all nations (especially

    those that are northward) that he seems to be

    disarmed of all humanity and to want the

    affability of expression who doth (when there

    is occasion for it) omit this benevolent

    insinuation of the hand.16

    Here, to be able to engage socially is to have a

    hand to gesture with, and the pun in Bulwers

    statement that one who fails to offer the hand is

    disarmed of all humanity seems to reinforce

    this. However, he had noted earlier that an arm

    lost, and likewise we are asked to recognize that

    it is not an animals different anatomy that

    excludes it from the realm of hospitality.17

    Rather, there is an incorporeal lack, more

    important than any corporeal one, which dis-

    counts animals from the social world that thehandshake opens up. The reason for the absence

    of animals from this sphere of friendship

    is because the handshake is, Bulwer states,

    a natural expression [which] seems to result

    from the sympathy between the will and the

    hands. For, the will [is] affectionately inclined

    and moved to stretch forth herself; the hand

    is moved by the same spirit.18 This gesture,

    as all gestures, is a manifestation of volition, and

    so animals can never be understood to speakeven physically because they are creatures lacking

    such will, which is a capacity of reasonable beings

    only. An animals body movement is mere

    corporeal noise while hands, Bulwer argues in

    Chironomia, are not only assistant to eloquence

    but do incredibly conduce to all the offices of

    reason and humanity.19

    Bulwer is not alone in his assessment of the

    body as a reflection of humanitys reasonable

    state. Such a belief gets played out in many worksin this period. Philosophical discussions linking

    reason and the flesh are constant and orthodox as

    the humoral make-up of the body was one way

    of understanding the mind of the individual.

    Robert Burton, to cite just one famous example,

    begins The Anatomy of Melancholy (1624) with

    a lengthy discussion of the human frame, seeing

    it as inseparable from his later discussion of

    human psychology.20 But this interest in the body

    can also be traced in a different way in other areas

    of early modern intellectual life. In the court

    masques of Jacobean and Caroline England, for

    example, the potentially reasonable nature of

    the human body is reflected in the centrality of

    dancing which was understood to be, as Blair

    Hoxby has written, the raison-detre of these

    court performances.21 In them, actual spoken

    dialogue played a minor role, something that

    apparently undermines the prioritizing of speech

    in the distinction of human from animal that can

    be found, for example, in George Puttenhams

    declaration that Poesie was thoriginall cause

    fudge

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    4/15

    before the people remained in the woods and

    mountains, vagarant and dispersed like the wild

    beasts.22 From this conventional perspective,

    humans gathered to tell tales and so society was

    born, whereas animals, beings without speech,

    cannot tell tales and so can never be conceived

    of as being properly social.

    Just as Bulwer argued for the possibility of

    ocular audition introducing the deaf to the society

    of the hearing, so an alternative way of commu-

    nicating another kind of speech was

    emphasized in the court masque. Dance itself

    was recognized in early modern theorization as

    conveying meaning. Jennifer Nevile writes:

    Dancing taught the chosen members of societycontrol over their body and over their actions,

    both when dancing and in day-to-day interac-

    tions with their colleagues and superiors.

    It was visible evidence that a person was

    capable of controlling their inner emotions

    as well. Dancing, therefore, functioned as a

    social marker, as one of the ways a certain

    group in society defined itself and excluded

    others.23

    We can go further than this, I think. If dancingmarks out class difference it also marks out

    species difference. Nevile writes that

    Movements of the body were believed to be

    the outward manifestations of movements of the

    soul. Consequently, if the movements of the body

    were ungraceful, then the movements of the

    soul would be presumed to be similarly ugly

    and inharmonious.24 Courtly dancing revealed

    a rational mind in that it reflected grace and an

    ability to act in accordance with socially agreed

    rules that is, the steps of the dance. An animal,

    lacking such a mind, was therefore incapable of

    such dancing, and a performance of a disorderly

    dance therefore said much about the species

    status of the dancer.25

    In the court masques of the seventeenth

    century, then, it was not only the tales told but

    also the dances danced that constructed human

    society, and this is marked in one trope of the

    masque in which a shift from the opening chaos

    of the antimasque to the order of the courtly

    dance at the end was presented as being

    to human. James Knowles, tracing the represen-

    tation of such less-than-humans (satyrs, animal-

    headed men) and apes in Stuart court perfor-

    mances, has noted that masque form, with its

    movement from antimasque to masque, was an

    ideal vehicle for demonstrating the primacy of thecivil, human, and royal over the barbarian,

    satirical, and bestial.26 Ben Jonsons Oberon

    The Fairy Prince offers an illustration of this.

    This masque was performed at Whitehall Palace

    on 1 January 1611. It opens with a scene all

    obscure, and nothing perceived but dark rock,

    with trees beyond it, and all wildness that could

    be presented. In this place a group of satyrs

    (played by professional actors) are gathering and

    running forth severally . . . making antic actionand gestures.27 They are awaiting the presence

    of Oberon (played by Prince Henry) who will,

    they hope, transform them: he will gild our

    cloven feet, Hang upon our stubbed horns /

    Garlands, ribands, and fine posies, stick our

    pricking ears / With the pearl that Tethys wears,

    Trap our shaggy thighs with bells.28 It is the

    animal aspect of the satyrs what reveals them as

    less-than-human that will, they hope, be

    overlaid by a civility which is symbolized in thejewels and ornamentation that the Fairy Prince

    will bring. But when Oberon enters the stage

    in a chariot, which to a loud triumphant music,

    began to move forward, drawn by two white

    bears his follower, the foremost sylvan,

    corrects the satyrs telling them that the True

    majesty in the room is James I and not his

    performing son.29 Silenus, the prefect of the

    satyrs, acknowledges this:

    He makes it ever day, and ever spring,Where he doth shine, and quickens

    everything,

    Like a new nature: so that true to call

    Him, by his title, is to say, Hes all.30

    Where Oberon has the power to superficially gild

    the satyrs lack of humanity, James can truly

    transform the world.31

    At this point in the masque the satyrs disappear

    from the action, and the remaining songs and

    dances are performed by fays (fairies), and

    by Oberon and his knights, who are played by

    early modern england

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    5/15

    of the presence of the rightful monarch has

    transformed the action and order is restored by

    the commanding gaze of the king. The best view

    of Inigo Joness staging was from the throne

    and thus, literally and figuratively, in the masque

    it is the sovereign alone who has the trueperspective.32 But the order that is present is not

    manifested in a shift in the spoken language of

    the text (the satyrs speak in rhyme, as do the

    fays). Rather, order is represented as visible,

    bodily. It is in the dance in the movement from

    the satyrs antic dance full of gesture to the

    controlled measures, corantos, galliards, etc.

    performed by the court at the end that meaning

    is conveyed.33 Puttenhams claim that it was

    poetry that brought human society into being isonly partly true. For Jonson and other masque

    writers, society is established through poetry but

    it is also constructed in physical performance:

    in adherence to the socially agreed rules of the

    dance.

    But it is not just in dancing and hand gesture

    that the body is used to construct a human.

    Bulwer argued that Two amphitheatres there

    are in the body, the hand and the head, and

    he planned, alongside his Chirologia andChironomia two further receptacles of his

    observations of human gestural language:

    Cephalelogia (the natural language of the

    head) and Cephalenomia (the Rule of the

    head: i.e., the qualification of all cephalical

    expressions, according to the laws of civil

    prudence).34 These texts do not exist, but

    Bulwers interest in the human head is a

    reflection of wider cultural conventions that are

    linked to ideas about dancing and gestural

    language. In a number of masques, and in other

    writings of the period, the face in particular

    emerges as a place where the human can be found

    and it is to this that I now turn. I will return to

    the writings of John Bulwer to his work on

    the musculature of the head, Pathomyotomia

    (which may be what became of his proposed head

    books) but I begin with another court text: John

    MiltonsA Masque Presented at Ludlow Castle.

    These are very different kinds of writing, but

    both reflect alike on the nature of species

    difference and the role of the face in that35

    losing face

    In 1634, Milton gained the commission to write

    A Masque Presented at Ludlow Castle. The

    masque was commissioned to celebrate the Earl

    of Bridgewaters becoming the President ofWales and the Marches. This role saw

    Bridgewater as Charles Is representative in

    Wales, a place which was considered wild and

    uncivilized, and . . . very far from the center of

    both power and culture.36 Involving the Earls

    three youngest children in key speaking roles, the

    masque took up the geographical location of

    Ludlow Castle itself and focused on the dangers

    of borderlands: between the wood and the court;

    the savage and the civil; but also between theanimal and the human. The central character of

    the masque, Comus, spends his time lurking in

    the dark woods for innocent passers-by whom he

    lures to join his immoderate gang by (appro-

    priately enough for the son of Bacchus and

    Circe) offering a drink: by tempting their fond

    intemperate thirst as the Attendant Spirit of the

    woods says.37

    The dramatic action of A Masque centres on

    the Lady who represents chastity, and was playedby the Earls daughter, the fifteen-year-old

    Lady Alice Egerton. She becomes separated

    from her two brothers in the wood and is

    captured by Comus and shackled by him to a

    magic throne where she refuses his advances. She

    is released only by the supernatural, immortal

    powers of Sabrina, the spirit of the river Severn,

    which borders Wales and England. The masque

    thus tells its moral story about temperance, but it

    is also speaking about the dangers and closeness

    of savagery, a typical conceit of this genre. But

    A Masqueis inevitably more modest than any of

    the court masques written for James or Charles,

    in keeping with its being presented in a provincial

    court rather than the royal one. The modesty,

    though, is also appropriate to Miltons focus on

    temperance in the text. While we begin with the

    antimasque of Comuss rout of monsters . . .

    making a riotous and unruly noise and end with

    the childrens victorious dance / Oer sensual

    folly and intemperance, this is no simple

    celebration of chastitys victory over lechery.38

    fudge

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    6/15

    already present in the figure of the monarch

    (as when, in Oberon, the change occurs with the

    satyrs discovery that James is and has ever been

    present). Miltons masque, rather, is a didactic

    work of art. By the end of the performance

    Comus and his followers have not been stopped,

    they are still lurking in the woods for the next

    thirsty traveller. The text is thus a warning to all

    viewers and all readers (it was first printed in

    1637). Its meanings are aimed at a political level

    in that the masque glances at the Earls work in

    maintaining order in the borderlands of England

    and Wales. But they are also aimed at an abstract

    level in that it touches questions of human

    moderation.

    A Masque Presented at Ludlow Castle alsoraises very interestingly the question of being

    human. For what happens to the intemperate

    passers-by who are tempted by Comuss poisoned

    cup is that they are changed; they are metamor-

    phosed in a very particular way:

    Soon as the Potion works, their human

    countnance,

    Th express resemblance of the gods, is

    changd

    Into some brutish form of wolf or bear,Or ounce, or tiger, hog, or bearded goat,

    All other parts remaining as they were.39

    Later the Attendant Spirit says that Comuss

    pleasing poison

    The visage quite transforms of him that drinks

    And the inglorious likeness of a beast

    Fixes instead, unmoulding reasons mintage

    Characterd in the face.40

    What the potion does, then, is take from the

    intemperate drinker the thing that marks them as

    human: their face. For Milton, the face represents

    the reason and divinity that sits within the human

    body. This is a trope he repeated inParadise Lost

    some thirty years later when Adam, discovering

    Eve has eaten the forbidden fruit, says: How

    art thou lost, how on a sudden lost, / Defaced,

    deflowered, and now to death devote?41 Like

    animals, so Adam believes, Eve is now wholly

    mortal, and she has lost her face, and thus

    her humanity has been ruined. Likewise, in

    is made more like the beasts than the angels by

    Comuss drink, something signified in the

    gaining of the animal head.

    The loss of face and reason has two related

    outcomes. First, we are told that the drinkers,

    all their friends, and native home forget / To roll

    with pleasure in a sensual sty.42 Their Circean

    animalization is represented through human

    isolation and the descent into the pleasures

    of the material realm. This transformation of

    human face into animal head mirrors that seen on

    the frontispiece to Thomas Heywoods

    Philocothonista, or The Drvnkard, Opened,

    Dissected, and Anatomized, a text printed

    in 1635, the year after the performance of

    A Masque.In this text, Heywood categorizes different

    kinds of drunkenness using different kinds of

    animals. Thus Ebrietas Ovina (sheep drunken-

    ness) is the category of those who when drunk

    seeme to be terrified with the feare of Sprites

    and Hobgoblines. Those who can stand upon

    no ground, but leape and dance, and caper, toy,

    laugh, sing, and prattle, troubling the whole

    company with their Antick gesticulations, and

    tedious verbositie are displaying EbrietasVitulina (calf drunkenness). Last in his list

    are the pig-drunks:

    These are most ridiculous and nasty, who by

    giving themselues over to all beastiall vinosi-

    tie, by spending whole dayes, and consuming

    night after night in Tavernes, and Tippling-

    houses, returne from thence, either led or

    carried, who oft times stumbling, lie wallowing

    in the kennells, and so appeare no other then

    Hoggs and swine, newly come durty anddawbed out of the puddles.43

    An earlier version of this listing of animalized

    drunkards can be found in Englands Bane: Or,

    The Description of Drunkennesse which was

    written by Thomas Young and published in

    1617. Young became tutor to the young John

    Milton the following year.44 The metamorphosis

    of Comuss rout in A Masque Presented at

    Ludlow Castle is thus a conventional one, and is

    one that is associated with drinking. Animals, this

    discourse states, live only in the sensual present,

    early modern england

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    7/15

    so losing control of ones reason when one is

    drunk is also and logically (not just metaphori-

    cally) a loss of humanity and a descent to the

    status of a beast.45

    But the second set of descriptions that is used

    to represent those who succumb to Comus is also

    worth noting. What goes alongside the question

    of lack of temperance and removal of face is a loss

    of something else. Comus refers to his followers

    as a herd.46 Throughout the piece which

    is 1023 lines long they are described only as a

    group: as a rout, a rabble. This is quite

    different from a society: a herd is a collection of

    by an outside force. A member of the herd

    in A Masque is tricked into joining and held in

    place by Comuss magic potion. They therefore

    have no agency and they cannot alter the nature

    of that rabble. In this context, an individual

    animal is an impossible singular in a collective

    noun the herd. It is as if, in A Masque, Milton

    is representing the power of the herdsman over

    the herd and, to speak more generally, of humans

    over animals, as being analogous to sorcery.

    The orient liquor in a crystal glass that Comus

    offers to passers-by is potable dominion.47 For

    the unknowing drinker, however, it is a truly

    Fig.1. Frontispiece fromThomas Heywood, Philocothonista, orThe Drvnkard, Opened,Dissected, and Anatomized(London:Robert Raworth,1635) The British Library Board. (Shelfmark C30d11).Reproduced with permission.

    fudge

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    8/15

    Comuss dupes drink the proffered refreshment

    and lose their reason, lose their faces and lose

    their individuality all in one movement, so much

    so that they fail to know this. After their

    transformation they, so perfect is their misery,

    / Not once perceive their foul disfigurement, /

    But boast themselves more comely than

    before.48 They have lost the ability to tell

    whether or not they are human. Once again

    Milton is not unique. Three years before his work

    was performed Jonson, in his masque Loves

    Triumph through Callipolis, wrote that slaves

    to sense were Mere cattle, and not men.49

    The animalization, like being human, has an

    internal cause. In A Masque one of the Ladys

    brothers outlines what happens to those who arenot temperate. He states:

    But when lust

    By unchaste looks, loose gestures and foul

    talk,

    But most by lewd and lavish act of sin,

    Lets in defilement to the inward parts,

    The soul grows clotted by contagion,

    Imbodies, and imbrutes, till she quite lose

    The divine property of her first being.50

    The human soul sunk in sensuality is imbodied

    and imbruted: it has become flesh and thus, in

    this conception, the human has become a mere

    animal. This is why gesture to return to

    Bulwer is meaningful only when underpinned

    by animating reason. Hence, when in Chirologia

    he mentions the horse-rhetoric of Smithfield

    and the very different fish dialect of

    Billingsgate, what he is referring to is the

    cunning management of the hand by mer-

    chants and traders at London horse and fish

    markets and not the body language of animals

    because animals, lacking reason, can never be

    understood to have such language.51 Thus, as

    speech, and therefore human status, is a product

    of reason, humans sunk in vice lose their essential

    humanity; they become animal-headed (a litera-

    lization of their beastly minds). But these humans

    also metaphorically lose their faces: they cease to

    know their friends and to know themselves and

    are, in Jonsons terms, mere cattle; in Miltons a

    herd. They are not active parts of a social

    grouping and they are no longer individuals, they

    are passive, isolated, bodily beings trapped in a

    world of physicality.

    This is presented on stage not in the speech of

    Comuss rout (for they, appropriately, have none,

    only riotous and unruly noise), but in theiranimal heads and their Midnight shout, and

    revelry, / Tipsy dance and jollity.52 Their sheer

    faceless bodiliness here is thus part of that other

    complex of ideas through which the human is

    being constructed in early modern thought:

    dancing. And dancing, as noted, is human.

    Jonson, indeed, termed dancing a display of

    the wisdom of your feet in his 1618 masque

    Pleasure Reconciled to Virtue that includes the

    character Comus, the god of cheer, or the bellyand is believed to have influenced Milton.53 The

    chaotic motions of the later Comuss followers

    exist in opposition to the organized dances

    performed by the children at the end of A

    Masque. These are dances that take place in the

    castle rather than the wood, thus marking also the

    spatial shift from animal outside to human inside:

    the woods being the place that Puttenhams

    storytelling humans left behind. Thus, we have

    various oppositions emerging in A MasquePresented at Ludlow Castle that are utterly

    orthodox in their rendition of Aristotelian ideas:

    between noise and articulate communication;

    between orgiastic gyration and orderly move-

    ment; between the woods and the castle; and

    between animal heads and human faces.

    But dancing can be read in another way as

    well. In the early modern period it was part of the

    education of a gentleman and was placed along-

    side horse riding as a truly human accomplish-

    ment. Indeed, according to John Holless father

    in 1614, to learn one skill alone was to be not a

    gentleman but a worker: to dance only belongs

    to a ballarin . . . and to ride only to a cavallerizzo.

    All must therefore go together.54 But once again

    it was not only class status that was at stake;

    species status must also be considered. Success in

    both dancing and horse riding signalled control:

    in dancing it was control over the animal self,

    the body; in riding, over the animal other, the

    horse.55 An orderly dancer, like a good horseman,

    revealed himself to be a controlled and

    early modern england

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    9/15

    controlling human.56 Thus, in Oberon, when

    Prince Henry enters the scene in a chariot with

    two white bears in harness and then performs

    a dance, he is revealing his humanity twice over

    and in a most spectacular fashion: he controls the

    wildest of animals, he controls himself.

    just nodding

    But on a more figurative level, riding a horse has

    another meaning. If to ride is to control nature,

    a control lost at the Fall, riding is therefore a

    return, if only temporarily, to a state of pre-

    lapsarian perfection. It is a moment of re-facing,

    you might say. And this way of thinking about

    riding can be found almost forty years afterJonsons masque to provide another way of

    linking equestrianism and dancing to possession

    of a face. In Pathomyotomia Or a Dissection of

    the significative Muscles of the Affections of the

    MindeJohn Bulwer states that he is interested in

    that which I use to call the Clock-work of the

    Head, or the Springs and inward Contrivance

    of Instruments of all our outward motions,

    which give motion and regulate the Dyall of

    the Affections, which Nature hath placed inthe Face of Man.57

    The mechanical imagery he uses does not displace

    the conception of the reasonable nature of the

    human face. In fact, so linked is the face with

    reason for him that in his outline of the Scope

    of the book, Bulwer states that his aim is to

    describe such Actions only, which are generally

    and universally used by all men, as apparent

    significations of their Mind.58 Animal actions

    are never of interest to him because they are

    never evidence of a reasonable mind, and because

    of this, animals are not considered as beings

    possessing faces. They can make meaning can

    express the sensual worlds they are engaged

    with but not like humans: It is well known

    that most of Creatures [sic] that have no

    Countenance to expresse the variation of their

    Sensitive Appetites and Imagination, do express

    their Senses by certaine motions or wagging of

    their Eares.59 This lack of expressive counte-

    nance is superficially due to the physical fact of

    an animals musculature: it is this, he states, that

    prevents them from laughing.60 But there is

    another and much more powerful reason for an

    animals lack of face, which is, as it was in

    discussions of hands in Chirologia, about what

    lies beneath the skin. Bulwer makes the claimthat animals have no Countenance on the

    level of the soul as well as the body. Indeed, the

    two the soul and the body are inseparable as

    it is the former that underpins his anatomical

    explanation as to how facial movements take

    place, an explanation which defines what he

    means by a face.

    Tracing what might be termed the bodily chain

    of command from the brain to the nerves to the

    muscles, Bulwer argues that all the parts ofthe body are under the rule of the soul: for the

    instruments move, because they are moved by

    it.61 The body is thus a microcosm of the royal

    court in which command comes from its king.

    In animals, the soul that moves is merely

    sensitive and mortal, whereas in humans, the

    soul is reasonable and immortal. Thus, in a

    circular argument, humans have faces because

    faces are sites of reasonable expression and only

    humans have reason, while animals, lackingreason therefore lack faces. An animals idiom

    (if such a word can be used) is always bestial.

    But this bestial idiom is available to humans too

    those animal-headed drunks in Heywoods text

    testify to the possibility (although they could not,

    of course, testify in court).

    This human beastliness is, then, of the soul as

    well as of the body, and a link between physique

    and mind in which animals lurked in the human

    flesh can be found not only in imaginative

    representation but in the science of physiognomy

    as well, a science which discovereth, as Bacon

    put it, the disposition of the mind by the

    lineaments of the body.62 In A Pleasant

    History: Declaring the whole Art of

    Phisiognomy (1613), for example, Thomas Hill

    states that he is considering in particular the

    brutish sort: which for the lacke of grace, and

    being not regenerated by Gods holy Spirit, . . . in

    such manner, are moued to follow their sensuall

    will and appetites.63 The grace that is lacking

    that he refers to is Gods grace the grace of the

    fudge

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    10/15

    soul but it is equally a grace manifest in the

    body. Instead of dancing, these unregenerated

    brutes simply move and follow their senses.

    Hill goes on:

    the Creatures which are regenerated throughthe holy Ghost, doe not onely endeuour to

    mortifie their fleshly appetites, but seeke to

    put away and correct, all other inormities

    and vices resting in them: although there still

    continueth a frailtie to sinne, and offences

    daily committed.

    Control is what humans, those regenerated

    beings, must try to achieve. They will, however,

    always fail, because they are human, but they

    must continue to try, because they are human.Their inherent and inevitable frailty is visible

    in the body and Hill writes, for example, that

    The person hauing a bigge forhead, is slow

    and dull Witted, compared vnto the Oxe, in that

    the Oxe is a slow beast, which hath a bigge

    forehead.64 What the science of physiognomy

    declares, then, is the fallen and dangerously

    fleshy nature of the human. Just as a dance can

    become an orgy and a rider can lose control

    of a horse, so a soul can be imbodied, andimbruted and a human face can become an

    animal head.

    This link between horse riding, possessing a

    face and being human is represented in two

    related ways inPathomyotomia.Firstly, Bulwers

    conceit for expressing the difference between

    voluntary (human) and spontaneous (animal)

    movement is philosophically cliched but also

    utterly appropriate.65 In humans:

    The Braine commandeth as soone as it hath

    judged whether the thing is to be avoided

    or persecuted, the Nerves commonly called

    Illatoresor the Posts, for the intelligence they

    give, bring the commandement, and Facultie;

    theMuscleillustrated with the Animal Spirits

    obeyes, and moves the part according to the

    command of the will: and as a Riderby the

    moving of his Raines, guides his Horse: so

    the force of the Soule residing in the Braine,

    moves the Muscles by the Nerves, as with

    Raines; for the will is like the Rider, the

    Nerves to Raines, and the Muscles to the66

    Thus facial expression and its readable language

    are, like riding, an externalization of the humans

    internal, rational capacity. When this capacity is

    gone, so too is human status. This can be seen

    in the animal-headedness of Comuss followers

    who have given-in to their sensual appetites,

    but Bulwer offers another vision of this using a

    different equine analogy, this time of a rather

    more shocking species: If any man would make

    triall to find after what manner this significant

    motion of the Head is done, having got a fresh

    humane carkasse, the other parts besides the

    ligaments of the vertebres being taken away, he

    should manoeuvre the head forwards and back-

    wards and watch the muscles move. These

    muscles which pull the head this way and thatare, he says, represented in the raines of a

    Horse. As if to make the point more fully,

    Bulwer advises his reader:

    nothing can better shew you how to conceive

    of the office and function of these Muscles,

    than if you should put a garter athwart about

    the hinder part of the Head, bringing it from

    above the ears on each side-down to the breast,

    for if you afterwards draw both the ends of

    the garter together, the Headwil give a justNod of assent: but if you pull the ends by

    turns one after another, you will cause

    Collaterall Nods, such as wee use when the

    partyes to whom we make the signe are on

    the one side of us.67

    The human carcass is bridled and thus made

    horse. This is philosophically correct: a human

    carcass is devoid of a soul as its immortal essence

    has flown and it thus lacks the reason that marks

    it as human. This means that, like those animals

    referred to as a herd, rout, or rabble, a human

    carcass has no agency, will, or reason. Its actions

    are dictated by an external power: an anatomist

    playing at being a rider rather than a herdsman,

    this time. But Bulwer does something else here as

    well. The head, he writes, gives a just Nod.

    It appears at first glance that even this de-souled

    body is capable of a reasoned reply. But this is

    soon corrected: the existence of Collaterall

    Nods reminds us that just here means simple

    rather than morally correct. In this discourse a

    early modern england

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    11/15

    animal-headed human, can never give a nod that

    is just because what can actually be seen when the

    muscles move, when reins are put on, is simply

    animal agitation.68

    But perhaps the fact that the human bridle

    Bulwer advocates here is working in reverse,

    leaving the rider pulling from the front rather

    than behind, is what allows for the glimpse of a

    possibility that a carcass is capable of moral

    judgement. Where riders can see and read only

    the body of the horses they are riding, sitting as

    they are on the animals back, this harnessed

    human-horse is always facing the anatomist who

    is holding the garter. Perhaps the equine imagery

    and the link between horse riding and human

    control that recurs in this early modernAristotelian discourse that I have been tracing

    has another meaning, and a much more literal

    one than I have yet considered. Perhaps we

    should read this discourse as always having been

    written from on top of the animal, and wonder

    what might have been written if another position

    had been taken: by an animals side, for example,

    or standing face-to-face with one.

    The former is a position neither

    Milton nor Bulwer consider, thelatter an impossible one, as for

    them a face is only ever human.

    notes

    1 Aristotle, Aristotles Politiques, or Discovrses of

    Government (London: Adam Islip,1598) 13.

    2 Aristotle, Politics, trans. Benjamin Jowett

    (Chicago: Encyclopaedia Britannica, 1952) II: 446,

    1253a9.

    3 Jacques Derrida, The Animal That Therefore

    I Am (More to Follow) in The Animal That

    Therefore I Am, ed. Marie-Louise Mallet, trans.

    David Wills (New York: Fordham UP, 2008) 11.

    4 Aristotle,Aristotles Politiques 13.

    5 For a more detailed account of these ideas in

    this period see Katherine Park, The Organic

    Soul 464 ^ 84 and Eckhardt Kessler, The

    Intellective Soul 485^534 in The Cambridge

    History of Renaissance Philosophy, eds. Charles

    B. Schmitt and Quentin Skinner (Cambridge:

    6 Francis Bacon, Of Friendship [1625] inEssays,

    ed. Michael J. Hawkins (London: Everyman, 1973)

    80. On the impossibility of human/animal friend-

    ship in early modern ideas see Erica Fudge,

    The Dog is Himself: Humans, Animals, and

    Self-Control inThe Two Gentlemen of Verona inHow To Do Things With Shakespeare, ed. Laurie

    Maguire (Oxford: Blackwell, 2008) 185^209.

    7 Sir Miles Sandys, Prudence, The first of the

    Foure Cardinall Virtues (London: W. Sheares, 1634)

    42^ 43.

    8 John Bulwer, A View of the People of the Whole

    World: Or, A short survey of their Policies, Dispositions,

    Naturall Deportments, Complexions, Ancient and

    Moderne Customes, Manners, Habits, and Fashions

    [aka Anthropometamorphosis] (London: ThomasGibbs, 1658),A Hint of theUseof thisTREATISE

    n. pag.

    9 Martha L. Edwards,Deaf and Dumb in Ancient

    Greece inThe Disability Studies Reader, ed.Lennard

    J. Davis (London and New York: Routledge

    1997) 35.

    10 John Bulwer, Philocophus: Or, The Deafe and

    Dumbe Mans Friend (London: Humphrey Moseley,

    1648) 102, 103^ 04. In this period, as earlier, deaf-

    ness and dumbness were perceived to be abso-lutely linked. Rene Descartes assumed this in

    Discourse on the Method when he wrote of men

    born deaf and dumb who invented their own sign

    language. Descartes, Discourse on the Method[1637]

    inThe Philosophical Writings of Rene Descartes, eds.

    John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald

    Murdoch (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1985) I: 140.

    The founder of precedent law in England, Edward

    Coke, links the status of a person non compos

    mentiswith a person incapable of language. Coke,

    Beverleys Case in The Reports of Sir Edward Coke

    (London: W. Lee, 1658) Part IV: 334^39. Emily

    Cockayne records the first deaf person drawing

    up their will as Framlingham Gaudy in Norfolk

    in 1672. Cockayne, Experiences of the Deaf in

    Early Modern England,The Historical Journal 46.3

    (2003) 507.

    11 Bulwer, Philocophussig. A4v.

    12 Ibid. sig. A3v. Other early modern thinkers

    interested in this are discussed in Dilwyn Knox,

    Ideas on Gesture and Universal Languages

    c.1550 ^1650 in New Perspectives on Renaissance

    Thought: Essays on the History of Science, Education

    fudge

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    12/15

    eds. John Henry and Sarah Hutton (London:

    Duckworth,1990) 101^36.

    13 John Bulwer, Chirologia: or the Natvrall Language

    of the Hand [1644], ed. James W. Cleary

    (Carbondale: Southern Illinois UP,1974) 6.

    14 Ibid. 5^ 6. The punning use of handle is an

    echo of Titus pun handle not the theme, to talk

    of hands in Shakespeares Titus Andronicus(c.1592).

    On the meaning of hands in early modern culture

    and a discussion of Titus Andronicus see Michael

    Neill, Amphitheaters in the Body: Playing with

    Hands on the Shakespearian Stage,Shakespeare

    Survey48 (1995): 23^50.

    15 In this way he is going beyond classical writers

    for whom, as Gregory S. Aldrete has argued,

    Gestures were an indispensable part of

    oratory and served many purposes. Hand

    and body motions could mirror the verbal

    component of an oration, impart emotional

    shadings to thewords, serve as an alternative

    language for communication, and enhance

    the innate rhythmic nature of many orations.

    Gesture truly offered a way for Roman

    orators to achieve eloquence not only with

    their words but also with their entire

    bodies. (Aldrete, Gestures and Acclamationsin Ancient Rome (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins

    UP,1999) 42^ 43)

    16 Bulwer, Chirologia91.

    17 Ibid. 22.

    18 Ibid. 88.

    19 John Bulwer, Chironomia or The Art of Manual

    Rhetoric[1644] inChirologia 155.

    20 A discussion of hands and agency in earlymodern thought that reflects on these ideas is

    Katherine Rowe, Gods handy worke in The

    Body in Parts: Fantasies of Corporeality in Early

    Modern Europe, eds. David Hillman and Carla

    Mazzio (New York and London: Routledge, 1997)

    285^309.

    21 Blair Hoxby, The Wisdom of their

    Feet: Meaningful Dance in Milton and the

    Stuart Masque, English Literary Renaissance 37.1

    (2007) 74.

    22 George Puttenham,The Arte of English Poesie

    [1589], eds. Gladys Doidge Willcock and Alice

    23 Jennifer Nevile,The Early Dance Manuals and

    the Structure of Ballet: A Basis for Italian, French

    and English Ballet in The Cambridge Companion to

    Dance, ed. Marion Kant (Cambridge: Cambridge

    UP, 2007) 13.

    24 Jennifer Nevile, The Eloquent Body: Dance

    and Humanist Culture in Fifteenth-Century Italy

    (Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana UP,

    2004) 2.

    25 In the philosophyof the fifteenth-century neo-

    Platonist Marsilio Ficino, dancing also had a role to

    play in constructing order. Thomas M. Greene

    writes: Ficinos magic was based on the doctrine

    that certain figures (figurae) enjoyed a sympathy

    with a given heavenly body, and could be used

    to attract its influence down to this world. Thesefigurae included dance, music and facial expression.

    Ficinos ideas were present, Greene argues, in

    sixteenth- and seventeenth-century English court

    dances. Greene, Labyrinth Dances in the French

    and English Renaissance, Renaissance Quarterly

    54.4 (2001) 1445.

    26 James Knowles, Can ye not tell a man from

    a marmoset?: Apes and Others on the Early

    Modern Stage in Renaissance Beasts: Of Animals,

    Humans, and Other Wonderful Creatures, ed. Erica

    Fudge (Urbana and Chicago: U of Illinois P,2004) 146.

    27 Ben Jonson, OberonThe Fairy Prince[1611] inBen

    Jonson: The Complete Masques, ed. Stephen Orgel

    (New Haven and London:Yale UP, 1969) s.d. (stage

    direction) 1^2, 27^28. Sir Miles Sandys wrote of

    satyrs that they might have the visage of men,

    but they want a reasonable soule, which is the

    sole difference betweene man and beast. Sandys,

    Prudence 42^ 43. Like the deaf as they are desig-

    nated in the law, these apparent humans are not

    human at all.

    28 Jonson, Oberonlines 73, 80 ^ 81, 83^ 84, 86.

    29 Ibid. s.d. 216 ^17; line 248. On the white bears

    and their history see Barbara Ravelhofer,Beasts

    of Recreation: Henslowes White Bears,English

    Literary Renaissance32.2 (2002): 287^323.

    30 Ibid. s.d. 30; lines 271^74.

    31 A similar representation of James can be found

    in Jonsons earlier Masque of Blacknesse (1605)

    in which the Britannia is Ruled by a sun that to

    this height doth grace it, / Whose beams shine

    early modern england

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    13/15

    Ethiop, and revive a corse (Complete Masques lines

    223^25).

    32 See Stephen Orgel, The Jonsonian Masque

    (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP,1965) 37.

    33 Jonson, Oberons.d. 206, 336.

    34 Bulwer, Chirologia6.

    35 The politics of these authors are also very

    different, and such differences might be traced

    in the texts themselves. Milton, in Paradise Lost

    in particular, recognizes that clarity ^ natural

    meaning ^ is gone forever and that human lan-

    guage is inherently fallen. InA Masque, too, words

    and gestures lie: Comuss disguise and false words

    signal this. Milton is also working within a political

    ideologyin which fixed hierarchy is not necessarilytobe upheld: in whichmetamorphosis of the social

    order is a positive possibility. Bulwer, on the other

    hand, distrusts slippery written and spoken

    language, and praises the language of the body as

    a natural language that has, somehow or other,

    managed to escape the curse at the confusion

    of Babel (he does not explain how). See Bulwer,

    Chirologia 19. Indeed, Jeffrey Wollock argues that

    Bulwer no doubt believed that [the deafs] more

    natural way of seeing the world made them

    inclined to support the King and the Laudianchurch, as opposed to what he considered the

    artificial religious and political interpretations

    that the Puritans superimposed on reality

    (Wollock, John Bulwers (1606 ^1656) Place in the

    History of the Deaf, Historiographia Linguistica

    23.1/2 (1996) 9).

    36 Stephen Orgel, The Case for Comus,

    Representations81 (2003) 32.

    37 John Milton, A Masque Presentedat Ludlow Castle

    [1634] in John Milton: Selected Shorter Poemsand Prose, ed. Tony Davies (London: Routledge,

    1988) 67.

    38 Ibid. s.d. 92, 974 ^75.

    39 Ibid. 68 ^72. Bruce Boehrer helpfully translates

    express here as meaningapressed out, externa-

    lized resemblance in an essay that emphasizes

    the Plutarchan influence on Milton. Boehrer,

    Milton and the Reasoning of Animals: Variations

    on a Theme by Plutarch, Milton Studies 39.2

    (2000) 54.

    40 Milton,A Masque526^30.

    41 John Milton, Paradise Lost[1674 ed.], ed. Alastair

    Fowler (London: Longman, 1968) Book IX: lines

    900 ^ 01.

    42 Milton,A Masque76 ^77.

    43 Thomas Heywood, Philocothonista, or TheDrvnkard, Opened, Dissected, and Anatomized

    (London: Robert Raworth, 1635) 4, 4 ^5, 6. The

    tedious verbositie of the calf-drunk marks their

    expression as voice rather than speech.

    Drunkenness is legally understood in this period

    to give the drunk a temporary status as

    non compos mentis. See Coke, Beverleys Case

    335^36.

    44 See Adam Smyth, It Were Far Better be a

    Toad, o r a Serpent, then a Drunkard: Writing

    about Drunkenness inA Pleasing Sinne: Drink andConviviality in Seventeenth-Century England, ed.

    Adam Smyth (Cambridge: Brewer, 2004) 199.

    45 Further discussion of human drunkenness and

    other dangers to species status are in Erica Fudge,

    Brutal Reasoning: Animals, Rationality and Humanityin

    Early Modern England (Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP,

    2006).

    46 Milton,A Masque 152.

    47 Ibid. 65.48 Ibid. 73^75.What Comuss herd experiences is

    hardly happiness at all. Doth the tickling of the

    body cause a happy life? Seneca asked in Epistle

    XCII. The answer is clear: Let that creature

    which is borne to eate, onely depart from that

    most beautifull number of liuing creatures, and

    next vnto the gods, and let him be numbred with

    brute beasts. Bodily pleasure is the pleasure of

    an animal. Seneca, The Workes of Lvcivs Annvs

    Seneca, Both Morall and Naturall, trans. Tho. Lodge

    (London: William Stansby,1614) 385.

    49 Ben Jonson, Loves Triumph through Callipolis

    [1631] in Complete Masques 89 ^90. Knowles has

    also noted the link between Miltons masque and

    Aurelian Townshends earlier Tempe Restored(1632)

    in which there are also animal-headed men.

    He argues that the less-than-humans of Tempe

    Restored must choose their direction of transla-

    tion, whereas in Miltons masque, the beast-

    masquers are animals without reason and

    unable to recognize their own bestiality, perhaps

    itself part of a critique of the courtly beast-mas-

    quers who falsely consider themselves rational

    fudge

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    14/15

    50 Milton,A Masque463^ 69.

    51 Bulwer,Chirologia85.

    52 Milton,A Masques.d. 92,102^ 03.

    53 Ben Jonson, Pleasure Reconciled to Virtue [1618]

    inComplete Masques239. The text continues: For

    dancing is an exercise / Not only shows the

    movers wit, / But maketh the beholder wise, / As

    he hath power to rise to it (240 ^ 43), and s.d. 5.

    On Jonsons influence on Milton see Orgel,

    Jonsonian Masque151.

    54 John Holles, Instructions for travel that my

    father gave me the 22 July 1614, cited by Barbara

    Ravelhofer, Virgin Wax and Hairy Men-

    Monsters: Unstable Movement Codes in the

    Stuart Masque in The Politics of the Stuart Masque,ed. David Bevington and Peter Holbrook

    (Cambridge: Cambridge UP,1998) 255.

    55 The other skill listed with dancing and riding

    that a gentleman was expected to learn was fen-

    cing, which, again, involves bodily control. See

    Holles,Instructions 255; Hoxby,Wisdom 76.

    56 Another kind of control of nature ^ gardening

    ^ was also an exercise in dominion and has been

    linked by Nevile to dancing. See Jennifer Nevile,

    Dance and the Garden: Moving and StaticChoreography in Renaissance Europe,

    Renaissance Quarterly52.3 (1999): 805^36. On gar-

    dens and human control see Andrew

    Cunningham, The Culture of Gardens in

    Cultures of Natural History, eds. N. Jardine,

    J.A. Secord and E.C. Spary (Cambridge:

    Cambridge UP,1996) 41^47.

    57 John Bulwer, Pathomyotomia Ora Dissection ofthe

    significative Muscles of the Affections of the Minde

    (London: Humphrey Moseley, 1649) sig. A2v.

    On this work see Thomas R. Geen and Louis G.Tassinary, The Mechanization of Emotional

    Expression in John BulwersPathomyotomia(1649),

    American Journalof Psychology 115.2 (2002): 275 ^99.

    58 Bulwer, Pathomyotomia 190.

    59 Ibid.

    60 Ibid.104 ^ 05.

    61 Ibid.12.

    62 Sir Francis Bacon,The Advancement of Learning

    [1605], ed. Arthur Johnston (Oxford: Oxford UP,

    1974) 103. This phrase is quoted directly by

    63 Thomas Hill, A Pleasant History: Declaring the

    whole Art of Phisiognomy,Orderly vtteringallthe speciall

    parts of Man, from the Head to the Foot(London: W.

    Iaggard, 1613) sig. A3r.

    64 Ibid. sigs. A3v, 31v.

    65 Bulwers unwillingness to allow humans to

    display anything but voluntary expression is a pro-

    blematic one, and at one point he makes the link

    between facial expression and an unwanted erec-

    tion. Bulwer asserts that there are two kinds of

    reason ^ vigilantiumanddormientium, So thatin

    every motion the will comandeth either manifestly

    or obscurely (Pathomyotomia110, 30). On the link

    between erection and expression see Stephen

    Greenblatt, Mutilation and Meaning, in Body

    in Parts234^35. Loss of control over the body as

    evidenced in sexuality ^ this time wet dreams ^ in

    A Masque Presentedat Ludlow Castle ^ is the subject

    of Deborah Shugers Gums of Glutinous Heat

    and the Stream of Consciousness: The Theology

    of Miltons Masque, Representations 60 (1997):1^21.

    66 Bulwer, Pathomyotomia 14.

    67 Ibid. 49, 50.

    68 The terminology used in early modern texts

    itself is interesting, as Brian Cummings notes, with

    the word animal itself in early modern dis-

    cussion divid[ing] in connotation: the animal

    on the one hand is a creature inhabited by

    anima, by a soul or living principle; on the

    other, the animal is a physical compound

    of organic, corruptible and mortal flesh.

    (Cummings, Animal Passions and Human

    Sciences: Shame, Blushing and Nakedness in

    Early Modern Europe and the New World

    inAt the Borders of the Human: Beasts, Bodies

    and Natural Philosophy in the Early Modern

    Period, eds. Erica Fudge, Ruth Gilbert and

    Susan Wiseman (Basingstoke: Macmillan,

    1999) 33)

    Erica Fudge

    School of Humanities

    University of Strathclyde

    7.28 Livingstone Tower

    26 Richmond Street

    Glasgow G1 1XHUK

    early modern england

  • 8/13/2019 1 OKI. EL ROSTRO HUMANO DE LA TEMPRANA EUROPA DE LA EDAD MODERNA. cfr Quevedo grotesco retrato dam

    15/15

    Copyright of Angelaki: Journal of the Theoretical Humanities is the property of Routledge and its content may

    not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written

    permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use.